Actions And Objects From Hobbes To Richardson
Jonathan Kramnick download
https://ebookbell.com/product/actions-and-objects-from-hobbes-to-
richardson-jonathan-kramnick-1894112
Explore and download more ebooks at ebookbell.com
Here are some recommended products that we believe you will be
interested in. You can click the link to download.
Actions And Objects From Hobbes To Richardson Jonathan Kramnick
https://ebookbell.com/product/actions-and-objects-from-hobbes-to-
richardson-jonathan-kramnick-51932354
Making Objects And Events A Hylomorphic Theory Of Artifacts Actions
And Organisms 1st Edition Simon J Evnine
https://ebookbell.com/product/making-objects-and-events-a-hylomorphic-
theory-of-artifacts-actions-and-organisms-1st-edition-simon-j-
evnine-5772442
Object Recognition Attention And Action 1st Edition Ingo Rentschler
https://ebookbell.com/product/object-recognition-attention-and-
action-1st-edition-ingo-rentschler-4405686
Actions And Invariants Of Algebraic Groups Second Edition Second
Edition Walter Ricardo Ferrer Santos
https://ebookbell.com/product/actions-and-invariants-of-algebraic-
groups-second-edition-second-edition-walter-ricardo-ferrer-
santos-6837258
Actions And Invariants Of Algebraic Groups 1st Edition Walter Ferrer
Santos
https://ebookbell.com/product/actions-and-invariants-of-algebraic-
groups-1st-edition-walter-ferrer-santos-882248
Actions And Reactions Kipling Rudyard
https://ebookbell.com/product/actions-and-reactions-kipling-
rudyard-3890468
Torus Actions And Their Applications In Topology And Combinatorics
Victor M Buchstaber And Taras E Panov
https://ebookbell.com/product/torus-actions-and-their-applications-in-
topology-and-combinatorics-victor-m-buchstaber-and-taras-e-
panov-5250074
Criminal Actions And Social Situations Understanding The Role Of
Structure And Intentionality 1st Edition Anthony Amatrudo Auth
https://ebookbell.com/product/criminal-actions-and-social-situations-
understanding-the-role-of-structure-and-intentionality-1st-edition-
anthony-amatrudo-auth-6844794
Nimesulide Actions And Uses 1st Edition Kim D Rainsford Editor
https://ebookbell.com/product/nimesulide-actions-and-uses-1st-edition-
kim-d-rainsford-editor-1819566
Actions And Objects From Hobbes To Richardson Jonathan Kramnick
Actions And Objects From Hobbes To Richardson Jonathan Kramnick
Actions and Objects
from Hobbes
to Richardson
Actions And Objects From Hobbes To Richardson Jonathan Kramnick
Actions and Objects
from Hobbes
to Richardson
Jonathan Kramnick
stanford university press
Stanford, California
Stanford University Press
Stanford, California
©2010 by the Board of Trustees of the
Leland Stanford Junior University
No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form
or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying
and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system
without the prior written permission of Stanford University Press.
Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data
Kramnick, Jonathan Brody.
   Actions and objects from Hobbes to Richardson / Jonathan
Kramnick.
      p. cm.
  Includes bibliographical references and index.
   isbn 978-0-8047-7051-4 (cloth : alk. paper) —
   isbn 978-0-8047-7052-1 (pbk. : alk. paper)
   1. English literature—18th century—History and criticism.
2. English literature—Early modern, 1500–1700—History and
criticism. 3. Act (Philosophy) in literature. 4. Philosophy of mind
in literature. 5. Causation in literature. 6. Philosophy, English—
17th century. 7. Philosophy, English—18th century. I. Title.
pr448.p5k73 2010
820.9'384—dc22      		
2010010565
Printed in the United States of America on acid-free, archival-quality
paper
Typeset at Stanford University Press in 10.75/15 Sabon
Contents
Preface    vii
	Introduction: Nothing from Nothing    1
1. Actions, Agents, Causes    27
2.	Consciousness and Mental Causation: Lucretius,
Rochester, Locke    61
3. Rochester’s Mind    99
4. Uneasiness, or Locke among Others    141
5. Haywood and Consent    168
6. Action and Inaction in Samuel Richardson’s Clarissa    194
Notes    233
Index    299
Actions And Objects From Hobbes To Richardson Jonathan Kramnick
Preface
This book is about the literature and philosophy of action during
the last half of the seventeenth and first half of the eighteenth cen-
tury, the period that begins roughly with Hobbes and Rochester and
ends roughly with Hume and Richardson. It features works that
examine what happens when someone acts, when someone writes
a letter or lifts her feet or kills or kisses, and so on. For many, the
difference between actions and other kinds of events turned on the
presence of mental states. Someone writes a letter because she wants
to communicate information and intends for her reader to under-
stand her. Her desire for the one or intention for the other causes
physical movements of various kinds. And yet how does a mental
state like desire or intention cause the body to move? This simple
question was of vast significance for all kinds of writers during the
period, and opened up literary and philosophical problems for our
time as well as theirs, from how a work of writing can represent
thought on the page, to how matter can be the locus of conscious-
ness, to whether minds actually cause anything to happen after all.
Writing about the mind during the period took many forms and
has been the topic of much important work in literary and intel-
lectual history. The relation between mind and actions, however,
remains relatively untapped and points in a number of unusual
directions. For example, although this book is above all interested in
the language of mental states, it does not make an argument about
the growth of inwardness or interiority or the psychological subject
during the period. Rather, considering actions leads in a different
Preface
viii
direction. Minds were understood to do many kinds of things—
from represent objects, to work through equations, to grieve—but
when they caused someone to act, they were understood to blend
in some fashion with the rest of the world. For some, this kind of
causal relation meant that minds were at bottom like everything else
in nature. When these writers considered actions, they were often
led to unexpected or unsettling conclusions: that the will might not
be free, that all matter might be sentient or nothing sentient at all,
that states of mind extend outside the head. For others, the topic of
actions provided an occasion to block just these sorts of conclusions
and to distinguish the place of mind and mental causes from other
parts of the world.
	The late seventeenth and early eighteenth century was indeed
a lively time for the consideration of actions, with the combined
emergence of empirical philosophies of mind and new literary forms
designed to feature experience in often startling ways. Against this
expansive backdrop, I follow the problem of actions from the cul-
tures of Restoration-era science to mid-eighteenth-century social
theory, from worries about political authority to the consideration
of a commercial society. While I place importance on what we
might call externalism, I also watch notions of the external shift
from physical bits of matter in motion to the elaborate networks of
law and exchange. My goal has not been to follow a single perspec-
tive as it grows to dominance, however, but rather to examine com-
peting models of mind and action across the period and into ours.
I thus examine writers who have been integral for literary studies
along with those whose ideas might challenge our expectations on a
number of topics: from where seventeenth- and eighteenth-century
writers looked to find the sources of actions to what kinds of enti-
ties they considered to be conscious.
Actions and Objects has been generously supported through-
out by Rutgers University. In the early stages, I received fellowship
help from the NEH, the William Andrews Clark Memorial Library,
and the Huntington Library. At the end, I was the beneficiary of a
Preface ix
wonderful year at the Stanford Humanities Center, which saw the
completion of this manuscript and the start of another. As I tried
out some of these arguments and readings, a few appeared in print.
Early versions of sections of Chapters 3 and 5 appeared in ELH and
a very different version of a section of Chapter 4 in the Yale Jour-
nal of Criticism. They have now been completely reconsidered and
rewritten, but trace sentences remain.
	One pleasure of taking some time to finish is accumulating so
many debts of gratitude. I’ve been extremely fortunate to test some
of these arguments among a superlative group of graduate students
over the years. I could simply not have written a word without their
questions, responses, and quarrels. My period cohort—Lynn Festa,
Paula McDowell, and Michael McKeon—has provided invaluable
feedback and conversation. Also at Rutgers, I’ve had the pleasure of
working with Billy Galperin, Colin Jager, Meredith McGill, Jonah
Siegel, Henry Turner, and Rebecca Walkowitz. The “Mind and Cul-
ture” seminar at the Center for Cultural Analysis provided a burst
of intellectual energy and renewal just when I needed it most; our
many guests and fellows will find their promptings and ideas scat-
tered over these pages.
	The same is true for the crew at Stanford, old friends and new:
John Bender, Terry Castle, Denise Gigante, Joshua Landy, and
Blakey Vermeule. It has come to seem that the broader eighteenth-
century world is an expansive set of fascinating interlocutors,
including Helen Deutsch, Sarah Ellenzweig, Marcie Frank, Jody
Greene, Sandra Macpherson, John Richetti, Helen Thompson, and
others who have listened to me talk about actions and minds over
the years and who have helped to shape the argument in ways they
might not realize. Parts of this book were delivered to audiences
at Berkeley, Johns Hopkins, Princeton, Rice, Stanford, UCLA, the
University of Chicago, and Yale, where audiences were curious and
receptive and challenging in the best ways. James Kierstead, Mike
Gavin, and my editor Emily-Jane Cohen all made it possible for this
book to come together in the end.
Preface

	It gives me great pleasure finally to thank those whose contin-
ued intellectual presence in my life I consider a tremendous gift:
Jared Gardner, Elizabeth Hewitt, Jonathan Goldberg, Adela Pinch,
Michael Trask, Michael Warner, and Bliss Kern. Bliss read the entire
book and made it better.
Actions and Objects
from Hobbes
to Richardson
Actions And Objects From Hobbes To Richardson Jonathan Kramnick
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing
Things happen. Often we try to explain them. When Edmond
Halley looked back on records of passing comets, he noticed that
one seemed to appear every seventy-six years. He then thought hard
about orbital velocity and gravity, drawing on what he knew about
mathematics and physics. When a fashionable young man cut off
a lock of hair belonging to a fashionable young woman, Alexan-
der Pope wrote a poem. He thought hard about human actions,
drawing on what he knew about motivation and desire. Halley and
Pope both understood that neither comets nor cuttings come into
the universe from nothing. Yet for Halley, the comet’s return didn’t
have anything to do with beliefs or decisions. The comet didn’t
choose to shoot by earth. Rather, its particular mass and distance
from the sun put it on an unalterable ellipse. For Pope, the cutting
of the lock had little to do with the properties of metal shears or
strands of hair. The Baron chose to cut Belinda’s hair. Pope would
like to know why he did so:
Say what strange Motive, Goddess! cou’d compel
A well-bred Lord t’assault a gentle Belle?
Oh say what stranger Cause, yet unexplor’d,
Cou’d make a gentle Belle reject a Lord?1
Were we to examine the Baron’s motives, Pope says, we might
discover why he cut Belinda’s hair. Were we to examine hers, we
might discover why she rejected his advances. Were we to do either,
we would learn how motives serve as causes, “am’rous Causes” to
be exact. Enclosed in the two couplets therefore is an implicit theory.
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing

Belinda and the Baron are agents. Their actions have causes. Among
these causes are states of mind. We may go even further. States of
mind distinguish actions like the rape of the lock from events like
the appearance of Halley’s comet.2
They do so because they serve a
causal role. States of mind make something happen, just like states
of physical matter. In other words, Pope plucks minds from other
kinds of things only to make us wonder how far the distinction
goes.
	This book is about minds and actions in Restoration and
eighteenth-century Britain. It examines how writers described what
precedes and constitutes an agent’s doing something, whether writing
a letter or fleeing a kingdom. The topic gathered new attention
during the period because it opened the possibility for a causal
theory of behavior in line with causal theories applied elsewhere in
the natural world. If desires, fears, beliefs, and so on were like causes
and actions were like effects, some said, then minds were similar to
other things in the environment; if minds represent the world in
motion, others responded, they were in some special sense distinct
from everything else. The discussion animated genres as diverse as
the treatise, the lyric, and the novel. Sometimes it concerned matters
as ordinary as the lifting of one’s feet; other times it engaged topics
as broad as what it means to be a person. In each case, the concern
was how states of mind might prompt, accompany, or follow the
movement of physical bodies. In this introduction, I will set out the
conceptual issues involved in the period’s consideration of actions.
I’ll then turn to a chapter-by-chapter summary of my argument. If
my sense of this book is right, several of my formulations may be
surprising, so I’ll present them in some detail.
	One might expect a book about minds to validate the long-
standing sense that the eighteenth century witnesses a new language
of inwardness or subjectivity associated with the joint rise of empiri-
cal philosophy and the novel.3
I complicate this thesis by pointing to
the largely unacknowledged role of external factors in the period’s
conception of mind. In the works I examine, the distinguishing
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 
feature of minds is the causal role they do or do not play in physical
movement. So while the writers I feature develop techniques to show
minds at work, their goal is to describe why certain actions occur
and how mental states fit into the rest of the world. The ostensible
privacy or interiority of mental states is often not an issue. We may
think of this as an important property of actions. Actions extend
mind into the world. Belinda might conceivably be thinking about
all sorts of things in the course of her day, from the taste of tea
to troubles with Betty. Pope is interested in why she rejected the
Baron, however, and so therefore looks at her reasons for doing so.
The same might be said for many of the well-known and incidental
actions mulled over in the writing of the period. Why did Evelina
accept Orville’s invitation to dance? Why did Moll steal that bundle?
Any time a writer asks why such an event happened, she pares
mental states into those fixed to behavior, the desires or beliefs that
form reasons for acting. To the degree to which literary history has
focused on inwardness or privacy, therefore, it has missed several
important features of mind-talk during the long eighteenth century.
This book looks closely at three such features as they take the
form of nagging questions: Are actions freely chosen or subject to
necessity? How do mental properties cause physical change? How
can a physical object be the locus of conscious experience?
Let’s start with the first question. The notion that human behavior
might be discussed in causal terms brought with it a serious entail-
ment. As soon as we know all the facts about Halley’s comet, we
understand why it has to appear every seventy-six years. The comet
doesn’t have any say in the matter. An inflexible confluence of causes
(mass, gravity, velocity, and so forth) rigidly determines its arrival.
The comet is subject to necessity. The question thus emerges with
some urgency if the same is true for actions. Were we to know all
the facts about the Baron’s cutting of the lock, or Belinda’s refusal
of the Baron, would we understand why each had to happen? Pope’s
language of causes suggests this may be so. Indeed, John Dennis
voices precisely this worry in his Remarks on Mr. Pope’s Rape of
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing

the Lock (1728), in which he complains that the word “compel” in
line six “is a Botch for the Sake of the Rhyme,” because it “supposes
the Baron to be a Beast, and not a free Agent.”4
Although he is
no friend to Pope, Dennis would still like to save the poet from
the charge of determinism. Surely Pope didn’t mean to say that the
Baron lacked freedom of the will. Pope’s emphasis on causation
suggests that Dennis was wrong. The poor Baron may have been
just as compelled as the comet, unable to do anything other than
cut. He too may have been subject to necessity.5
Writers like Dennis worry that necessity is a sort of alibi for
reprehensible behavior. Don’t punish me, the Baron might say; I
couldn’t have done otherwise. The assumption is that if one isn’t
free to choose one’s actions then one can’t really be held responsible
for them. The freedom that allows agents to take responsibility for
what they do is, on this view, incompatible with the necessity that
says they could never have done otherwise. One major contribu-
tion of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century theories of action was,
however, precisely not to pose freedom and responsibility against
necessity. It was rather to show how the two could be compatible.
Traditionally credited to Hobbes, compatibilism of this kind has
had great influence up to the present day.6
The argument works by a
series of redefinitions. First among them is freedom itself. “Liberty
or Freedome,” Hobbes writes, “signifieth (properly) the absence of
Opposition” or “externall Impediments of motion.”7
On this view,
freedom does not refer to an ability to choose or will actions. Rather,
freedom refers to an ability to perform actions once they are chosen.
While “no Liberty can be inferred of the will, desire, or inclination,”
we can infer a “Liberty of the man; which consisteth in this, that he
finds no stop, in doing what he has the will, desire, or inclination
to doe” (146). A will may no more be free than a thought may be
brittle or a square may be fast. In contrast, an action is free when it
may be brought to completion, confined when it is impeded.
	This redefinition was useful for Hobbes because it put the freedom
of actions together with the safety provided by the state. Absolute
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 
power was not a threat to liberty; rather, it provided the protection
for agents to act as they would choose.8
Despite changes in political
theory over the course of the period, the idea that freedom could be
compatible with necessity had considerable endurance. Hume for
example defined liberty as “a power of acting or not acting, accord-
ing to the determinations of the will” and then argued that this
power in no way conflicted with universal causation: “We cannot
surely mean, that actions have so little connexion with motives,
inclinations, and circumstances, that one does not follow with a
certain degree of uniformity from the other, and that one affords
no inference by which we can conclude the existence of the other.”9
Surely, he says, we cannot imagine that the will is indifferent to
motives or that motives don’t serve as causes. Liberty requires only
that actions may be completed. For Hobbes, the state performs this
role by allowing for common safety and enduring contracts; for
Hume a society of commerce and reciprocity draws the behavior of
one person to the interests of another. In either case, the will finds
its place in a lattice of causes, and actions come under the same fine-
grained analysis as the rest of nature.
Although the compatibilist account of agency looms large in the
history of philosophy, with canonical British writers like Hobbes,
Locke, and Hume at front and center, its importance for questions
of literary history has not been much explored. One goal of this
book is to do just that. The topic of reasons for acting might be of
interest for how we think about such things as the writing of literary
character and the placing of actions into narratives.10
Compatibil-
ism in turn might be of help to refining our sense of how dependent
characterization was on notions of internal psychology and how far
it extended outward into external objects and events. I mentioned
earlier, for example, that talk about actions brought mental causes
into the world rather than separating them from it. I would add to
this thesis that compatibilism brought the world into the mind. As
a matter of definition, no cause ever exists on its own. Causes are
paired to effects and, presumably, caused by something else too.
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing

With respect to mental states, this means that reasons for acting
extend from experiences or desires or intentions to external objects
and back. It is not so hard to see how reasons might be internal.
The Baron desires that Belinda’s hair be cut. Belinda hopes for the
Baron to go away. While the lock and the Baron exist independently
of the mind, each is at the same time an object of a propositional
statement. They change according to the presiding mental verb (or
attitude, as we would now say): the lock is cut in the first case,
the Baron ushered away in the second.11
Mental states are thus
able to bear content, like a lock of hair, and mediate behavior, like
closing a pair of scissors.12
It is perhaps not quite so easy to see how
these same states might reach beyond the person. No small part of
my argument, however, will depend on the period’s sense of this
possibility. In different ways, Hobbes and Hume both say that every
event or object or idea links to another in a long chain of causation.
There is no way to view any one precisely on its own, since each has
antecedents and effects. With respect to mental states, the result of
this intuition is that ideas and intentions ultimately make their way
to the social and physical environment. When this relation tightens
some, the social or physical hookup actually plays a causal role in
this or that action. In our present example, we need only look at
the system of external rules and meanings that jointly govern the
behavior of the Baron or Belinda. “Am’rous Causes” reach through
things like cards and hair and forms like courtship and epic.
	I will be interested in accounts of actions that stress the connec-
tion between subjective experience and the environment or that
show how the meaning of concepts is fixed on the outside or that
tie volitional states like desire or intention to physical states like
the movement of particles. I will argue in other words for the
importance of what I’ll call externalism in the literature and philos-
ophy of the period.13
In many of the cases I look at, the emphasis
fell on causation as the means by which mental states or proper-
ties have at once a real existence and are looped into other things.
Even as causation promised to join mind to the world, however, the
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 
precise relation between the two became subject to some worry. The
question here—the second on my earlier list—was whether mental
states instigate physical change. One might be surprised if they
didn’t.14
Pope’s question about the Baron would only make sense,
after all, were his motives able to bring about his cuttings. Yet for
all the apparent simplicity of this sort of episode, it became clear to
a variety of writers that the process was difficult to pin down. Here
are Locke’s droll comments on the matter:
My right Hand writes, whilst my left Hand is still: What causes rest
in one, and motion in the other? Nothing but my Will,—a Thought
of my Mind; my Thought only changing, the right Hand rests, and
the left Hand moves. This is matter of fact, which cannot be denied:
Explain this, and make it intelligible, and then the next step will be to
understand Creation.15
Locke’s hand has been writing for some time. It has been forming
letters from ink, words from letters, sentences from words, and
paragraphs from sentences. The paragraphs read as more than
accidents. They make a certain sense and so seem to be the product
of an intending agent. Try as he might, however, Locke cannot
exactly describe how his will executes the writing. (I can’t either.
I’m telling myself to type this on the keyboard. So far my fingers are
moving as I’d like them to. How and why are beyond me.) Locke
does not dismiss the efficacy of mental properties or consign them
to a separate kind of substance.16
Rather, he considers the causal
relation between will and writing to be “a matter of fact” and to
be an example of a kind of relation that underpins every single act
done with deliberate intention. His amused caution has to do with
figuring out how the pieces of the causal puzzle fit into each other.
Does the relation between will and hand-movement have the same
features as the one between, say, heat and the evaporation of water?
The evaporation of water from heat happens every time the tempera-
ture crosses a certain threshold. The turning of letters into words
happens by fits and starts, according to a will described as a distinc-
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing

tively mental property. Locke is therefore sure of two things: that
he experiences the decision to move one hand and then the other,
and that his experience causes the movement of his hands. There is
something that it feels like for him to will hand movement. There is
nothing that it feels like for heat to evaporate water. In the face of
this sort of relation, however, Locke (as it were) throws up his hands.
He knows it exists yet cannot provide an intelligible description of
how it happens. Analytic philosophers would call this a problem of
mental causation.17
It is essential to every chapter of the book.
	Mental causation is so important because without it there would
be no concept of agency and no description of actions, only events.
It is important because the scene that Locke provides an expository
accounting of here reappears in different guises across the litera-
tures of the period, from the search into the “am’rous Causes”
beneath and before the rape of the lock to the prolonged question-
ing of the motives of a character like Clarissa Harlowe in doing
things like writing to Lovelace and leaving her family home. It is
important finally because of the very bafflement Locke so limpidly
voices. Attempts to resolve the problem of mental causation came
in a variety of forms: from the idea that mental states or properties
might have no causal role to play—epiphenomenalism as it is now
called—to the notion that external objects and events do the causing
for us; from accounts of the mind’s free and independent force on
the material world to a recognition that causal relations are best
inferred from an outsider’s stance. The pleasure in considering this
problem over the course of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries
has not, however, been in watching a single answer take shape from
the various responses. It has been rather in following the arguments
as they take off from their several sources, from Hobbes to Hume,
Rochester to Richardson, and in between.
At the heart of the problem of mental causation is the distinction,
if there is one, between mind and matter. For most of the writers I
consider, the causal relation at issue is not one between two kinds of
substance. For some the distinction is between mental and physical
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 
description, with the underlying substance question ruled out by
metaphysical fiat; for others the problem is fitting the mind into a
world that is wholly material; for still others a ghost does in fact
haunt the machine. The concerns raised by these responses take me
to the last of the three questions I raised earlier. Were we to ask who
cut Belinda’s hair we would think it odd if someone were to reply
the scissors. Why would we think so? On a first pass, we might say
because the Baron is a person and the scissors an object. We might
then hang a series of further distinctions on this difference. Persons
have a kind of value and set of rights, for example, while objects do
not. Junk the Baron’s scissors and he might be annoyed, but you’re
unlikely to be arrested. Drown the Baron in the Thames and you
might be held accountable for a crime. The concept of person is,
as Locke will say, a “forensic category,” useful for the assigning of
blame or praise, reward or punishment.18
But to say that persons
cause things to happen and objects do not is to take as a premise the
difference in roles one is trying to explain. Why then do we say that
a person has causal powers while a pair of scissors does not? For
many during the period the answer was that persons have conscious
experience.19
There is something that it is like to be the Baron.20
There is nothing that it is like to be a pair of scissors. Here we can
perhaps take matters no further. A person is a kind of thing that is
conscious; a pair of scissors is a kind of thing that is not. Full stop.
	The premise of this sort of argument is actually twofold. It
says that persons have consciousness and that consciousness
distinguishes one person from another. This claim is made with
tremendous influence in chapter 27 of Locke’s Essay Concern-
ing Human Understanding (1690). For Locke and others, talk of
consciousness was hard to have without talk of personal identity,
and likewise bringing up personal identity was hard to do without
having something to say about consciousness. One linked series of
conscious moments wraps the whole into a single entity, making
(as the case may be) the young Locke an identical person to the old
one. If consciousness and personhood go together, however, they do
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing
10
so with some interesting points of tension. For some writers, includ-
ing Locke on occasion, consciousness was something that bodies
have and do. It was not a separate substance put into them. But
how can a physical system be the locus of experience? Matter seems
by definition to be without experience, yet put together in certain
ways it gives rise to sentience, awareness, pleasure, pain, appetites,
and the like. In contemporary work on the mind, the question of
how this is possible is known as “the hard problem of conscious-
ness,” and it remains decisively unanswered to this day.21
Following
a single thread in the treatment of actions has thus backed me into a
large area of concern, one that I try to keep tightly laced to reasons
for acting. This topic includes consciousness because it is conscious
objects that would seem to have reasons. How precisely that is so,
however, does take us into really interesting and difficult issues.
	One such issue comes directly out of the seventeenth and
eighteenth century’s version of today’s “hard problem.” It went
something like this: assuming that material entities are able to have
the sort of experiences that lead to actions—conscious reasons
for acting, let’s say—why are some entities conscious and others
not? At bottom, there is little difference between the Baron and the
scissors (or the comet). Each is a composite of particles. Yet Baron-
particles give rise to consciousness and scissor-particles do not. In
the chapters that follow, I will look at a few works that directly
ask why that is so. Once again, my interest is not only with period-
defining answers but also with some difficulties encountered along
the way. I am especially drawn to texts that come at problems of
consciousness from an oblique angle or that offer radical or at least
off-center responses to the problems at hand. I’ll be interested in
texts that try to bring consciousness and personhood together, but
I will also be interested in those that pry them apart, that present
conscious experiences without a person having them or persons
without conscious experiences in train. I’ll be interested, finally, in
texts willing to follow their premises to seemingly unusual conclu-
sions, such as all things having some sort of consciousness or
(conversely) nothing having consciousness at all.
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 11
Keeping an eye toward the unexpected conclusion has provided
one way to narrow a path through a topic as broad as the literature
and philosophy of actions. It is also, I think, what happens when
you watch writers wrestle with nearly intractable quandaries: An
action is the kind of event whose cause includes mental states, but
what, after all, does “whose cause includes” really mean? A person
is the kind of entity that has consciousness, but how and why is
that so? Answer me these and perhaps you will, as Locke says,
explain creation. Two guiding principles are at issue here. Questions
of agency and consciousness have long concerned literary study in
general and the study of Restoration and eighteenth-century litera-
ture in particular. I attempt to look closely at the component parts
of one critical feature of this concern: how reasons, intentions, and
other states of mind do or do not serve as causes for acting. This
feature then opens up a number of related topics about minds and
persons and contexts for acting. The principle is to engage large,
period-defining concepts of character or consciousness, such as they
are, through incremental examples and debates. The second princi-
ple reflects somewhat on the first. I am inclined to tilt the applecart
rather than hold it in place. So where the predominant model has
favored the growth of inwardness, sympathy, and subjectivity, I tend
(again) to favor things external, like the elemental parts of matter or
the chains of causes or the forms of contract.
With the exception of the first chapter, this book moves freely
between what in retrospect we would call philosophical and literary
writing.22
I take great pleasure in the nonexistence of this distinction
in the eighteenth century, a period when David Hume could say his
ruling passion was a “love of literary fame” and Samuel Richardson
could say that he wrote “instantaneous Descriptions and Reflec-
tions” of minds and hearts at work. I view this overlap of concerns
as permission to stipulate a relation between texts that have grown
to seem far-flung. I do track allusion, citation, and debate, but
in the main my method has been to follow the appearance and
movement of problems, especially those concerning the antecedents
to actions and the ontology of persons and objects. These topics
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing
12
obey no boundaries of genre, though they are framed in different
ways according to the formal properties and needs of the texts in
which they come into view. So, for example, an epistolary novel
might choose to distribute its account of causes between writers of
letters, while a third-person fiction might try to represent a charac-
ter’s reasons or intentions; a piece of discursive prose might develop
a theory in explicit conversation with antagonists while a court
satire might make such dialogue internal to its lines. I arrange this
movement into a loose chronology: from a new attention to actions
amid dynastic anxieties and civil war to a concern with minds and
behavior amid polite and commercial exchange. With this backdrop
in place, it has been on occasion important to put the texts slightly
out of sequence or to put some writers in more than one chapter. I
do this to draw out concepts that might otherwise be obscured by
a stricter sense of order. I don’t think that much is lost in histori-
cal presentation by doing so; but the alternative would, I believe,
make topics like mental causation and consciousness a little more
difficult to track. These topics are of intense interest for Restora-
tion and eighteenth-century writers. At the same time, they have
been subject to concentrated attention in contemporary philosophy
of mind and cognitive science. While I focus on Restoration and
eighteenth-century texts, therefore, I also draw now and again on
the persistence of these concerns into our time. Sometimes this is to
illuminate older texts with our latest philosophy and science; just as
often this is to use the past to shine a light on the present. In either
case, I prefer to bore into texts rather than to present a survey. After
the first chapter, the rest are case studies, looking at texts that place
matters of actions interestingly in the foreground or that have been
important for the constitution of the field.
The first chapter presents an overview of the philosophy of action
from Hobbes to Hume and features three flash points in a century-
long debate over free will. I begin with a quarrel among Civil War
exiles, turn to a pamphlet war between Anthony Collins and Samuel
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 13
Clarke fifty years later, and end with David Hume’s reflections on
commercial society. The points of contention among the first two
sets of writers concern what the world is made of and whether
mental states have a causal function in a person’s behavior. Thomas
Hobbes and Anthony Collins argue that everything is composed
from a single, physical substance and therefore that a chain of cause
and effect connects every one event or object to another. On this
view, desires and fears have properties like atoms and apples, includ-
ing the ability to cause agents to act. John Bramhall and Samuel
Clarke respond that human agents will their own actions but are
themselves not willed. On this view, actions happen outside the laws
of causation that apply to physical objects, and human souls bear a
spiritual substance different from other kinds of stuff. For his part,
Hume pays attention to physical matter only to draw an analogy to
actions in the social world. We never know precisely what happens
when a physical cause yields a physical effect. Likewise, we never
know precisely what happens when a mental cause does the same
thing. In either case, we use our habits of inference and correlation
to presume a relation between the one and the other. We observe
something happen in nature and infer its material cause; likewise,
we observe an agent doing something and infer its mental cause.
The stance with respect to either is from the outside, as the private
cause of any given effect recedes from view.
	The long debate over free will concerned not only what happens
when a person acts but also from what stuff persons are made and
from what point of view it is best to describe actions. Over the course
of the debate, the meaning of several key terms changed. Hobbes
and Hume, for example, share what I call an external outlook on
actions. Yet what counts as the external changes from law, reward,
and punishment in the mid-seventeenth century to commerce and
interpersonal exchange a hundred years later. For Hobbes, one’s
recognition of legal and political forms provided reasons for acting,
while for Hume the elaborate networks of a commercial society
were necessary to complete actions and make them intelligible to
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing
14
agents. This difference in perspective might be described, I argue, as
one between a first- and third-person view. In the first case, an agent
adjusts her desires and intentions to fit into an order of rewards and
punishments; in the second, an agent looks at the actions of other
people to infer how reasons serve as causes. Likewise, Bramhall and
Clarke both defend human autonomy from external determina-
tion, yet the former does so in the name of the soul and the latter
does so in the name of common sense. Bramhall engages Hobbes
in a quarrel at the not yet established borders of philosophy and
theology; Clarke engages his readers’ sense that they are more than
lumps of matter.
	The second chapter takes a close look at this relation between
persons and physics. The topic is the role of consciousness and
mental causation in a universe reducible to particulate matter and
structured by physical laws. I say close look because, unlike the first
chapter, I slice thinly through a series of late-seventeenth-century
texts, looking in particular at Lucretian ideas of matter and agency
and a few responses they provoke. I begin with Thomas Creech’s
1682 translation of Lucretius’ De rerum natura, the first complete
translation of the poem published in English, and examine how
the poem presents the emergence of whole objects from individual
parts, thought from thoughtless atoms, and free movement from
a universe of causes. I then trace these concerns to two writers
subject to extensive treatment in later chapters. I compare Roches-
ter’s translation of a few lines of the poem to Creech’s and examine
their separate views of determinacy. I finish with a look at Locke’s
long discussion—one equally influential and pained—of conscious-
ness and personal identity in the Essay. The question broached by
this chapter has two parts: how can insentient matter be the locus
of thought and experience, and how can experience play a causal
role in the material world? I’m interested in Lucretius because his
poem tracked consciousness and mental causation to the movement
of particles. The poem proposes that composite entities—people,
trees, cows, what have you—take shape from the collision and
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 15
adhesion of invisible and indivisible atoms. One trouble appears
when the poem considers how atoms without thought can give rise
to objects that have thought. The solution works through a process
of emergence, wherein certain kinds of atoms interlock with others
in such a way that consciousness comes out of them. A second area
of concern appears when the poem considers what role conscious-
ness has in the physical universe. The answer here is most curious.
The poem makes a case for free will by distributing agency to the
manifold of particulate matter. Individual atoms are thoughtless,
yet they are at the same time possessed of will manifested in their
random and unpredictable movement. So where the first response
looks at sentience as an emergent property, the second looks at will
as present in all things, a perspective we would now call panpsy-
chist.23
	Such attention to the small units of matter was of evident interest
to Rochester, who translated two bits of Lucretius on his own along
with a piece of Seneca about the “lumber” from which all things are
made. Both Lucretius and Rochester write past the larger entities
in which consciousness and will are incarnated. They are interested
in particles, not persons. Locke’s treatment of consciousness and
personal identity in the Essay presents a very different view. In what
is arguably the first consistent use of the word “consciousness”
in its modern sense as “the perception of what passes in a Man’s
own mind,” Locke argues that consciousness provides a consistent
sense of self.24
Particles come and go but selves persist over time.
Accordingly, conscious selves anchor persons who are responsible
for their actions and subject to eventual reward and punishment.
Having made the topic of consciousness distinct from the topic of
matter, however, Locke returns to their relation in the closing books
of the Essay. There he engages what I describe as an early consider-
ation of today’s “hard problem.” How is it, he asks, that conscious
experience could arise from matter without experience? His answer
follows the conundrum to its several ends. Perhaps emergent proper-
ties are a brute fact of the world, or perhaps all matter bears some
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing
16
sort of experience, or perhaps matter is interwoven with spirit after
all.
	The third chapter picks up on the discussion of Rochester begun
in the second and spends considerably more time looking at how his
poetry engages questions of consciousness and causation, actions
and personhood. I feature Rochester because his poetry engages
the physical view he encountered in Lucretius and yet extends the
discussion to contexts for acting in the social and political world of
the Restoration. A Satyr against Reason and Mankind, for example,
asks whether mental states are able to cause anything or whether
they ride along with physical causes. It toys with the idea that
consciousness is only something left behind once physical causes
have done all their work, or that mental causes might exist but only
without agents to whom they belong. In a similar vein, Love and
Life presents composite objects that have spatial parts—a hand of
a person, a branch of a tree—but no equivalent temporal parts.25
An object (on this view) neither passes through time nor stretches
over time, but exists only in a kind of impossible present. These
musings about causation and existence over time combine in the
more sexually explicit poetry—like The Imperfect Enjoyment and A
Ramble in St. James’s Park—where mental states at turns get in the
way of the physical system or provide a language for the system’s
failure. My purpose in these readings is to show how Rochester
attempts physical explanations in terms of the movement of matter.
I also examine how he similarly attempts external explanations in
terms of the importance of context and environment. The physical
and external tend to combine or run in support of each other. Even
so, Rochester doesn’t so much make neat statements on these topics
as range over their many problems and difficulties, often to odd
and surprising effect. For example, despite his reputation for having
established desire as a basis for action, he mostly locates desire in
every place beside the heads, bodies, or persons found in his poems.
In keeping with this external view of an ostensibly inner phenom-
enon, I draw the chapter to a close by exploring the strange fate
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 17
of a couplet concerning mental causation from Artemiza to Chloe
that was cited in a variety of works in post-1688 London. My
question here is, How does a new context change the meaning of
lines committed to the importance of context? The answer takes us
from the manuscript coteries of the Restoration to the print public
of the 1710s and ’20s, and from poetry to the essay and novel.
	The Rochester chapter provides one route into the eighteenth
century. The fourth chapter on Locke’s theory of action provides
another. Locke’s theory of consciousness had stated that there is
something that it is like to have one or another thought, that the
background hum of the subjective provides the underpinning of
a person’s identity over time. What, if anything, do first-person
thoughts or feelings have to do with acting? In Locke’s first pass
at this question, the answer turns out to be “not much.” The first
edition of the Essay says that we may come to full understanding
of an action by observing it from the outside. One has reasons to
do something and those reasons lead to actions. What it feels like
to have some sort of reason has no causal role to play. The entire
history of an action may therefore be plotted from an external
perspective as a doing of some thing in order to accomplish some
good. Locke’s frustration with this argument emerges at the outset
in a series of letters exchanged with William Molyneux between the
first and second edition. Molyneux asks why agents are sometimes
led to error or to act against reason. He also poses to Locke his
famous thought experiment about a blind man suddenly provided
with sight. The point of the thought experiment—the Molyneux
Problem, as it will be subsequently known—is to emphasize the
importance of first-person experience in understanding the external
world. The blind man comes to new knowledge about the cubes and
spheres he had previously touched when he sees them for the first
time. The analogous suggestion for a theory of actions is that one
learns something new about them in light of the feelings with which
they were accompanied. The second edition of the Essay takes this
new argument to heart and presents a thoroughly revised model of
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing
18
actions. In the first edition, the cause of any action was always one’s
reason for doing whatever one did. In the second, it is always one’s
wanting to achieve some desired end. Alongside this new emphasis
on desire as a causal faculty, Locke places a new term—“uneasi-
ness”—which describes what it feels like to desire something. Seen
from the outside and the third person, desire is the cause of actions.
Seen from the inside and the first person, desire is experienced as
uneasiness. Without having a sense of this uneasiness, one can’t tell
exactly what any given agent will do or has done. Consciousness
provides additional information to what one gathers from observ-
ing the behavior of agents.
	This view is in some ways compatible with what we sometimes
think we know about early-eighteenth-century literary history.
So the chapter ends with a brief treatment of Catharine Trotter,
a playwright and novelist who also wrote a treatise in defense of
Locke’s philosophy. I don’t turn to Trotter just to track the contro-
versies surrounding the publication of the Essay. (Trotter’s was
one text among many written against or in defense of Locke at
the time.) Rather, I’m interested in Trotter because she provides a
concrete example of the explicit and sign-posted theory of actions—
the kind of thing that would appear in a treatise—making its way
into the implicit staging ground of narrative fiction. Trotter had
one foot in each. One of the selling points of the kind of epistolary
fiction Trotter wrote was that it provided a first-person perspec-
tive on causes of action. Locke had said that desire causes actions
and is experienced as uneasiness. Trotter’s novel and others like it
attempted to color in what that might mean and how it might work.
Assertion of this kind has often led to a related claim that novels
express the priority of the psychological and of a particular person’s
private experience, an argument associated with Ian Watt’s famous
book on the novel, though perhaps one as old as serious consider-
ation of the genre. I don’t intend to overturn this argument so much
as give it a little bit of trouble. The final two chapters of the book
are thus focused on eighteenth-century fiction and attempt to show
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 19
how a causal account of actions might or might not make recourse
to the interior states of agents.
	I’ve chosen two authors whose works seem to feature problems
of agency in interesting and opposed ways, and who are, respec-
tively, a subject of intense, recent interest and a perennial favorite. I
look at Eliza Haywood because she sustains the sort of commitment
to experience and feelings that Locke and Trotter promote without
also committing herself to accompanying notions of the interior
point of view or the separateness of personhood from environment.
Few writers of the period are more extravagant than Haywood in
their language of passionate feeling. So much is intuitively obvious.
My argument will be that Haywood stops short of assigning these
feelings to discrete persons or objects. The common-sense bonding of
experience to a subject of experience begins to loosen across a range
of incidents but is especially fraught and intriguing, I argue, with the
concept and experience of consent. Consent is a term understood
by Locke and others to join private experience to formal contracts
like marriage or impersonal structures like the state. In these
highly significant venues, it validates external authorities with the
imprimatur of the subjective. I wasn’t dragged to the altar; I freely
consented to marry this toad. The reign of this king or parliament
isn’t arbitrary; we consent to be governed. And so on. The trouble
is how to get from the possession to the expression of consent. How
do we know if someone actually consents? How do I know that I
have consented? The question poses the real quandary of accessing
mental states, phenomena that are difficult, some said impossible,
to view directly. The “How can I know if someone has consented?”
question is, in this respect, a sharpened version of the “How can I
see what another person is thinking or feeling?” question. Locke’s
answer is that you can’t and so you don’t. He outlines instead two
forms of externalization: the actual “expression” of consent in
forms of contractual stipulation, like oaths, charters, and vows, and
the tacit enacting of consent in daily life. I’m especially interested in
“tacit consent” because it attaches such a consequential entailment
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing
20
to the most quotidian of activities. One person buys an item in a
store; another takes a turn in a carriage; both have consented to be
governed. Out of the minutest incidents of mental causation rise the
grandest edifices of liberal democracy.
	Between mental causes and civil societies are a series of finely
grained steps: the kind of dailyness of thought and action dwelt upon
in works of fiction. Such will be my gambit, at least, in considering
Haywood’s Love in Excess (1719) and Fantomina (1725). These
will be unsurprising picks for anyone who has been paying attention
to the directions of eighteenth-century literary studies for the past
decade, and that is partly my point. Our attention has been drawn
to these works because, among other things, they are interested in
teasing through the kind of problems addressed by the dual nature
of consent, as something mental and something external. Locke’s
problem concerns the enactment of internally held mental states and
concepts. Haywood’s response is to show that there is no we or
I doing the consenting, or, in a slightly different vein, to say that
consent is in the doing, not in the expressing. One should, I think,
be careful about generalizing across kinds of writing. After all,
Haywood does not have the same kind of expository obligations as
Locke. Instead, she uses the advantages of formal experimentation,
especially in third-person evocations of tremulous feeling, to show
how mental states are as much in the world as in the head, as much
subject to the needs of plot as something one brings to other people
or larger institutions.
Readers might expect an account of Richardson to pursue an
opposite line of argument. Arguably no writer of the period is more
conventionally associated with first-person experience and the
authority of the self in advance of external circumstance. That is not
the argument I make, but neither do I simply pursue the contrary
line and suggest that our most storied novel of first-person experi-
ence really places mental states outside the mind or the person. I
end with Clarissa, rather, because its multiperspective version of
epistolary form is so suited to explore the several models of action
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 21
available in the eighteenth-century thought world. With this ending
in mind, I return to the basic ontological question around actions
with which I began, now pitched toward a work of fiction written
a century after the discussion of agency took off with Hobbes. The
ontological question is, How do we pick actions from the larger
class of events? The answer (again) is that actions involve mental
states while other events do not. Discussion of the nature of actions
thus turned on the status of this involvement. Did mental states
cause actions, and if so were they also caused? From what point
of view—internal or external, first or third person—should actions
be described? Clarissa zeros in on these questions by presenting
them from more than one vantage, as the few yet weighty events in
the novel come under painstaking description from several angles.
The novel makes clear, for example, that another way to ask about
actions is to count them. We ask about events in general when we
ask if anything has happened; we ask about actions in particular
when we ask whether anyone has done anything. Clarissa is particu-
larly interesting in this regard because so much of the tension comes
down to enumeration.
	Consider the conflict at Harlowe Place. Clarissa’s family treats
her refusal of Solmes as an act against them; Clarissa doesn’t
consider her refusal an action at all. The quarrel isn’t just over
why she has done one or another thing; it is firstly whether she has
actually done anything. So Clarissa finds herself explaining to her
family that she hasn’t taken any action against them, while they
view her as continually acting in ways contrary to their interests.
To help make sense of this conflict I make recourse to an updated
version of the eighteenth-century philosophy of action, Elizabeth
Anscombe’s famous account of intentional actions as those “under
a description.”26
One point of Anscombe’s little volume, Intention
(1957), was to show how actions come into view when the question
“Why?” is asked of them. Events present themselves as a mass of
unincorporated detail. Put them under a description and the focus
sharpens some. A young woman’s legs move up and down. A pair
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing
22
of shoes covers itself with mud. A young woman gets into a carriage
with a young man. A young woman runs away with a libertine. A
libertine kidnaps a young woman. These are separate accounts of
the same thing. The shoes get dirty as her legs move as she gets into
the carriage as she runs away or is kidnapped. Depending on which
description you choose, the event seems very different; indeed, only
in the latter two accounts is the event at all recognizable in the terms
suggested by the novel. So then the quarrel over enumerating actions
revolves around whether and how one apportions intentions in the
description one provides. The last two accounts subsume the earlier
ones because they provide the intention with which the action is
done, and (crucially) the intention belongs to a different agent in
each.
	Clarissa’s way of protecting herself is often to deny a causal role
in the actions she appears to take. I did not mean to fly away with
a libertine or to harm my family or to lose my honor. I certainly did
not cause any of these things to happen. She may have intentions
but they are rarely intentions with which any actions are done; they
are more likely to be intendings to do some future thing. This to say
that Clarissa holds on to an internal view of actions and tends to
avoid causal accounts of her own behavior. The “direction of fit,”
as readers of Anscombe would put it, is world to mind.27
Clarissa
attempts to “fit” the world to her intendings. The conflict with
Lovelace that preoccupies the middle sections of the novel appears
when the “direction of fit” moves in the other way, as Lovelace
attempts to shape intendings to a world that precedes them.
Richardson writes of Lovelace, in this respect, as one committed to
an externalist account of mental states. Nowhere is this more heated
than in the consideration of consent. Lovelace arranges appear-
ances and circumstances so that it seems that Clarissa has already
consented to lose her virtue and voluntarily live with him out of
wedlock. He is frustrated and aghast when her consent does not fit
the situation at hand. Both Lovelace and Clarissa are committed
to the notion that mental states individuate actions. On his view,
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 23
mental states emerge out of necessity from the causal order in which
they are placed, so the appearance of Clarissa’s consent should be
the same as the existence of her consent. On her view, one’s experi-
ence of one’s mental states is prior to their place in any outside order
of things. Clarissa is a nice place to end, in this respect, because
the ongoing discussion of actions both shapes and is responded to
by some of the features we have come to recognize as integral to
the midcentury novel, especially in the Richardsonian mode: from
claims to first-person authority, to the contesting friction of overlap-
ping perspectives. In this case, the competition between the several
accounts of action takes off against the view that would see them
as compatible with determination. For his part, Lovelace wants
nothing to do with the notion that anyone’s behavior is both free
and determined. Intentions are supposed to conform to the world
in the manner of a belief. For her part, Clarissa insists on her power
to act even as it becomes impossible to do so. Intentions outlast the
environment they face. The novel is thus among other things a vast
tapestry woven around the idea of compatibilism first set forth a
hundred years earlier.
	I close the book with a consideration of Clarissa’s death because
it is in the novel’s reflecting on whether the death is a suicide that
the topic of actions joins to the problems around consciousness and
mental causation I feature at the beginning. Clarissa wants to die
yet will not kill herself or act in any way that furthers her demise.
The avoiding of suicide thus picks out mental properties from the
flux of physical causes. Death is one among many physical events.
The prohibition against suicide—like that against murder—alights
on the mental and, in so doing, fastens on its causal role. The clarity
in which this may be stated reveals something interesting, I argue,
about the final sections of the novel: mental causation is easier to
envisage when it is related to the destruction of the person, precisely
the entity imagined to be the locus of such causes. This is not an
isolated phenomenon. The long consideration of Clarissa’s possible
suicide occurs at a historical moment when the materialist question-
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing
24
ing of personal identity had reached the topic of ending one’s life.
First codified in Augustine’s ruminations on Lucretia, the prohibition
against suicide takes as its premise that a person is distinct from her
physical body.28
On this view, Clarissa is not just a mass of atoms;
she is an entity made in imitation of God. Yet on the view of others
(including Hume), the prohibition against suicide marks out mental
causes only to make them superfluous, rendering the providential
design of the causal order something that ought not to be disturbed
by states of mind. For some, even, the appropriate response was
to say that persons were no different from any other composite
entity and mental causes the same as their physical counterparts.
On this view, the destruction of the person is merely the return of
matter to the cosmos from which all things are made. This is not
the view provided by the novel, of course, which endeavors to show
how Clarissa is not only more than her parts but also more than a
person in the conventional meaning subscribed to by other writers
in her midst. The answer the novel provides to the twin problems
of consciousness and mental causation thus turns out to be less of a
normal or conventional one than one that is, in its own way, just as
peculiar as those seen earlier in Rochester and elsewhere.
It is possible to imagine a world in which there are only events and
no actions.29
It is not likely that we, or anything like us, would be in
this world. But nevertheless such a world is possible. Subtract every
agent and this counterfactual world looms into view: earthquakes
happen, comets shoot by, and yet no one does anything. There
probably wouldn’t be any mental properties in this world, and if
there were, they would be causally inert with respect to the pageant
of events in their midst. Everything would be caused by physical
properties alone. This world has a kind of simplicity and elegance.
It is, however, not the world we live in. Were it so, I would not be
writing this sentence nor would you be turning these pages. The
actual world is one in which some events have mental causes. When
we pick these events out, we, as the expression goes, carve nature
Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 25
at its joints.30
We pare some events into actions, a class defined
by their causal history. My argument is that the century roughly
between Hobbes and Hume or Rochester and Richardson did just
that, and in so doing endeavored to discover the component parts
of actions in a way analogous to the discovery of anything else in
nature. Once upon a time this sort of argument might have been
made with particular reference to the interior life of characters or
voice of poems, a life or voice that corresponds to something like
the motives and mental causes of human agents. Perhaps for this
reason, when Anscombe sought to discount motives in her study
of intentions, she said in passing, “I am very glad not to be writing
either ethics or literary criticism, to which this question belongs.”31
For Anscombe, motives along with mental causes were inherently
obscure, whereas intentions could be read off the surface of one’s
behavior. An intentional action is not a series of doings plus an
inner, private motive. It is rather the kind of action for which one
may supply a description of why it was done. Anscombe’s attempt to
analyze an ostensibly mental-state term while holding at bay catego-
ries of the mind is crisp and seductive. Even so, it is perhaps a virtue
of writing literary criticism that one sees how even the more mind-
centered works of the period do not necessarily imply a language
of privacy or inwardness, selfhood or the individual. Some of the
works I feature are interested in these categories, but just as many
are not. What I will argue in the following chapters is this: the topic
of actions involved mental terms (including intentions) as a particu-
lar kind of cause. A close look at all kinds of texts shows that these
causes move in several directions, sometimes from within but just
as often from without. It is (again) possible to imagine a world that
has only events, with no actions. It is very difficult to imagine a
world that has no causes. Admitting causation into the account of
actions left a shudder. The works I look at are a few instances where
that shudder is most intriguingly recorded.
Actions And Objects From Hobbes To Richardson Jonathan Kramnick
1 Actions, Agents, Causes
The period covered by this study witnesses an important debate
about actions. For writers like Hobbes and Hume, human behavior
really ought to be described in causal terms. When trying to make
sense of what a person does, it is always best to examine the reasons
that cause and explain her actions. These reasons typically turn
out to be the desires and beliefs an agent has about the effects of
her actions, attitudes that are in turn caused by events external to
the agent herself.1
The view that actions are caused by attitudes
like desire and belief comes under scrutiny, however, from those
who think that causal arguments put at risk one’s autonomy and
freedom, especially when causes are understood to track back to
the outside world. While Hobbes and Hume found causal necessity
to be compatible with freedom, their opponents saw freedom as
incompatible with any sort of external dependence. My goal in this
chapter is to show how this debate encloses a range of philosophi-
cal, social, and literary concerns. Foremost among them is whether
persons are special kinds of agents, endowed with immaterial souls,
or whether mental states like desire and belief are made of the
same stuff as the rest of the world and thus susceptible to a kind of
limitless causation. Within this metaphysical quarrel over person-
hood, talk about reasons for action—one’s motives, say—often
entailed further talk about the societies in which actions occur. As a
result, debates about agency had considerable bearing on questions
of authority in an age that begins with civil wars and ends with a
commercial empire. To look at the motives that lie behind actions
was for many to examine how states of mind bring about forms of
Actions, Agents, Causes
28
politics or society. Yet states of mind like motive or intention were
often impossible to understand apart from the context in which they
occurred. And so the moral of this chapter for the larger project of
the book is this: if the philosophy of action consistently found itself
tugged between an account of agency that secluded the will within
the mind and an account that derived it from external causes, so
too did the literary forms designed to evoke the reaches of human
consciousness and action. In either case, the line between persons
and their component parts, persons and society, the mind and the
body, one mind and another, all come under meaningful pressure.2
Free Will or Necessity, Part 1
	Our story begins with Royalist exiles living in Paris during the early
years of the Civil War. In 1645 William Cavendish, the Marquess of
Newcastle, commissioned Thomas Hobbes and the Anglican theolo-
gian John Bramhall to write on the free will problem, a venerable
concern of philosophers made relevant again by religious and politi-
cal upheaval. Bramhall composed a short paper that spring and
Hobbes responded quickly; Bramhall rebutted, and the exchange
remained for a time within a small group of expatriates. Upon
their return to England, however, the debate took a more public
face. In 1654 Hobbes’s paper was printed and published, without
his permission, under the title Of Libertie and Necessitie. Bramhall
followed the next year by publishing his rejoinder, A Defence of
True Liberty, from Antecedent and Extrinsecall Necessity. Hobbes
replied with a new paper, The Questions concerning Liberty,
Necessity, and Chance, in 1656. Two years later, Bramhall returned
with Castigations of Mr. Hobbes his Last Animadversions in the
Case concerning Liberty, and Universal Necessity. By this time, the
debate had moved from a manuscript coterie to a print public and
in the process taken on the formal dimensions of a major contro-
versy, with each writer stating his theses in point-by-point response
to the other and anticipating and refuting arguments in advance.3
Actions, Agents, Causes 29
	Much of the controversy centered on how one might go about
defining what actions are, where they start and where they stop.
When Hobbes describes an action, he refers to an event with a causal
history. Agent P has done action R for reason Q. It is not enough
to say that P had Q while doing R; rather, in order to be part of
the description, Q must explain the occurrence of R. Consider the
following set of events: “[W]hen a Travailer meets with a shower,
the journey had a cause, and the rain had a cause sufficient to
produce it, but because the journey caused not the rain, nor the rain
the journey, we say, they were contingent one to another” and not
related as cause and effect.4
The conclusion Hobbes wishes to derive
from the example is simple. The rain happened at the same time as
the traveler’s journey but did not cause him to go, an action that was
presumably caused by the desire to get from one place to another.
The weather and a person’s decisions each have a causal structure
that prominently features reasons. This structure bears on the free
will problem because it tethers the will to something on its outside.
The agent who decides to go on a journey does so for a reason, and,
that being the case, her will has locked onto whatever disposition
or attitude explains her action. “In this following of ones hopes and
fears,” Hobbes writes, “consisteth the nature of Election,” by which
he means that choosing to act refers to a cause (a hope or fear) and
does not occur on its own.5
So when a philosopher leaves London
for Paris in the midst of civil war, he does so presumably because he
wants to be in Paris and believes that traveling to Dover and getting
on a boat is a good way of getting there. He may further believe,
given his Royalist sympathies, that being in Paris is a good idea in
the hour of Republican victory. Adding further reasons, however,
only sews more stitches to the causal net. It’s enough to say at this
point that he left because he wanted to be in Paris, for by describing
events this way we commit to the idea that “all actions have their
causes” (Questions, 70).
	To describe an action that an agent performs, one needs to
provide the reason for which it was done. One can do so, Hobbes
Actions, Agents, Causes
30
argues, by looking at the sundry passions of the mind, in particular
those organized around “appetite and fear . . . the first unperceived
beginnings of our actions.”6
This use of a mental vocabulary is
important (for the moment) to satisfy the requirement that the will,
like everything else, has a cause. We have on Hobbes’s account
provided a description of his decision to take a boat to Paris if we
say he feared the Parliamentary army and wanted to be safe among
friends. Our description of his actions, however, makes an argument
against his will having been free to take them. That is because
providing a causal account of actions also supplies the grounds
of their necessity, the locking of choice onto the attitude by which
it is explained. When, for example, Hobbes argues that the Lord
having said to David, “I offer thee three things; choose thee one of
them, that I may do it unto thee” (2 Samuel, 24:12), is not evidence
for free will, he claims that one cannot show that “such election
was not necessitated by the hopes, and fears, and considerations
of good and bad to follow” (Libertie, 7). God affords to David
the opportunity to choose among options, but the act of choosing
one thing over another requires there to be a reason for doing so,
and this requirement locks the will onto the particular hope or fear
that rationalizes the choice. Seen this way, the idea of free will is a
category mistake, since it ascribes to an appetite a condition that
can belong only to an agent, and since it attempts thereby to shed
the causes that explain why one takes the actions one does.
	Bramhall holds in contrast that “all the freedom of the agent is
from the freedom of the will,” a position he articulates in opposi-
tion to causal accounts of acting.7
We have sufficiently described
an action, on his view, if we say merely that it was undertaken by
the will. No lattice of causes trails behind this singular faculty.
And so while agents may be said to have reasons for acting the
way they do, those reasons never quite exert the force of a cause
into an effect. A reason might “representeth to the will, whether
this or that be convenient” but the will always retains the right to
choose what to do in response to this information (Defence, 10).
Actions, Agents, Causes 31
When “the will is mooved by the understanding,” for example, it
is “not as by an efficient, having a causall influence into the effect,
but only by proposing and representing the object” (Defence, 31).
In the gap between the reason that proposes objects and the will
that acts upon them lies the vaunted freedom from necessity, for
“whatsoever obligation the understanding does put upon the will, is
by the consent of the will, and derived from the power of the will,
which was not necessitated to moove the understanding to consult”
(Defence, 30). Where Hobbes tracks motives into actions, therefore,
Bramhall reverses course and sets the will apart from any motive
one might have, as if the will were a kind of person within the mind.
The result is an elaborate allegory of agency, in which “the will is
the Lady and Mistris of human actions, the understanding is her
trusty counseller, which gives no advice, but when it is required
by the will” (Defence, 30–1). Lest this seem too close to a cause
moving into an effect, Bramhall further observes that “if the first
consultation or deliberation be not sufficient, the will may moove
a review, and require the understanding to inform it self better”
(Defence, 31).8
The effort is at once to sheathe the will from causes
and provide for it a kind of psychology of choosing. To be a person,
on this view, is to be possessed of a will that can refuse to follow
motives or desires. Thus the proper tense in which to describe acts
of a free will is the past conditional. Despite the preponderance of
causes, free agents “might have suspended or denied [the] concur-
rence” of past actions or might “have elected otherwise” (Defence,
11, 209).9
	One important corollary of Bramhall’s account of actions is
that their proper description really ought not to extend beyond the
agent. Insofar as the will is always free to do otherwise, the history
of an action should make reference to events within the mind only.
In pointed contrast, Hobbes argues that the description of actions
should be as extensive as possible. This kind of description, as we
have seen, begins by making reference to reasons. Hobbes got on
a boat because he wanted to get to Paris. Agent P did action R for
Actions, Agents, Causes
32
reason Q. The more closely one looks at Q, however, the more one
sees that it is caused by Q1, Q2, and so on. Hobbes wanted to get
to Paris because he feared for his safety in London. He feared for
his safety in London because he believed his writings had angered
the Parliamentary authorities. Once opened up to inspection, the
causal horizon is nearly limitless. “That which I say necessitateth
and determineth every action,” Hobbes writes, “is the sum of all
those things, which being now existent, conduce and concurre to
the production of that action hereafter, whereof if any one thing
now were wanting, the effect could not be produced” (Questions,
80).10
The sum of all things can stretch quite far. At the very least,
it can extend beyond the minds of agents to the circumstances and
contexts in which agents find themselves. So while it is true that
actions depend upon mental states, it is also true that mental states
arise from objects, events, and occurrences, from causes external
to the head. When Hobbes writes that “nothing taketh beginning
from itself” he means to include not only the will but also what
we might think of as the efficient cause of the will, the attitude
to which the will is locked. Both are brought about by causes not
of the agent’s “disposing” (Questions, 289). While propositional
attitudes like wanting to get to Paris or believing that a boat might
do the trick may seem like they begin within us, as mental terms
ostensibly should, their proper description, Hobbes argues, ought to
reach from the mind to the world. This is because stopping with the
mind’s internal repertoire of attitudes would fall short of the story
in which one comes to have attitudes locked to actions. The route
accordingly moves from the outside in: “[E]xternal objects cause
conceptions, and conceptions appetite and fear”—and appetite and
fear the various acts of the will.11
	This particular dimension to Hobbes’s quarrel with free will is
worth a moment’s pause. The locking of the will onto attitudes like
wanting or fearing, knowing or believing, had seemed to commit
Hobbes to a kind of inward account of actions, one that specified
their causal history in terms of a mental vocabulary of desires or
Actions, Agents, Causes 33
intentions. But on further inspection it turns out that Hobbes is
equally committed to describing the history of actions with respect
to their peripheral beginnings, in contexts beyond the person.12
The long-term result, I will argue over the course of this book, is
a balancing of events internal to agents with the external forms by
which these events are shaped. Causation casts too wide a net to
capture only the propositional attitudes leading up to actions. So it
will be important for us to keep an eye on the varieties of external-
ism that begin for our purposes with Hobbes and extend into the
middle of the eighteenth century with Hume—to look, that is, at
accounts of action that track attitudes past agents having them to
the worlds from which attitudes spring, to societies and polities,
to physical units of matter, or simply to other people.13
Hobbes’s
version, as we have seen, places emphasis on the near limitless
reach of causation, the “sum of all things” that issue into a particu-
lar action. “There is hardly one Action, to the causing of which
concurres not whatsoever is in rerum natura,” Hobbes writes, and
then adds as if to explain, that “there cannot be a Motion in one
part of the World, but the same must also be communicated to all
the rest of the World” (Questions, 239). Hobbes thus elaborates a
concept of cause that binds atoms to thoughts to persons to kings to
God. On this view, actions don’t so much begin with agents as fall
backward along a continuous web.
	The inclusion of any one action within a web of antecedent
causes makes an important statement about the nature of persons,
as Hobbes’s critics were wont to show. If causation doesn’t begin
with the will, but rather with attitudes and before that with reasons
for those attitudes, then the special place of the person in the
overall scheme of the cosmos has been taken away. On the most
basic sense of things, Hobbes does not consider persons to be differ-
ent in substance from other entities in the world. His description
of the universe—in which “every Object is either a part of the
whole World, or an Aggregate of parts”—admits of one substance,
reducible in all instances to the atoms that make up minds and
Actions, Agents, Causes
34
bodies alike.14
I will explore in the next chapter some of the difficul-
ties that come with this sort of physical model of consciousness and
mental causation. I would like now to stick to the place of agents
in a world where action occurs as a motion across a single chain.
Consider Bramhall’s writing a response to Hobbes. Bramhall ascribes
to this act a “moral” foundation that begins within him. Hobbes
retorts, “I doubt not but he had therefore the Will to write this
Reply, because I had answered his Treatise concerning true Liberty.
My answer therefore was (at least in part) the cause of his writing,
yet that is the cause of the nimble local motion of his fingers. Is not
the cause of local motion Physical? His will therefore was Physically
and Extrinsecally and Antecedently, and not Morally caused by my
writing” (Questions, 142–3). The turn to reasons outside the agent
flanks an emphasis on physical description. One motion across the
surface of things takes us from Hobbes’s writing to the movement
of Bramhall’s fingers to the appearance of another essay, all without
much pause for a person having a will that expresses itself in writing.
When Hobbes adds to this account that “what it is to determine a
thing Morally, no man living understands,” he gets rid of the chance
that there might be something in agents—a moral center—that stops
the motion of cause and leaves space for an authority over one’s
own will (Questions, 142).
	Bramhall’s feeling that his essay has no cause other than his will
to write it, and that having this will is quite close to what it means
to be human, misrecognizes on Hobbes’s view the nature of causal
relations in a physical world. There is no space outside of matter
that belongs to the soul or the will or the passions or anything else
one might want to use as a platform for autonomy.15
Hobbes asks
Bramhall to give up the intuitive sense that he is the cause of his
own actions and that any particular action he performed could
always have gone otherwise. Bramhall’s error, in other words, is
to hew too closely to common sense—“that which he sayes, any
thing else whatsoever, would think, if it knew it were moved, and
did not know what moved it”—rather than to look into the sources
Actions, Agents, Causes 35
of his actions (Questions, 41). The feeling one has of free will is
intuitive only if one is ignorant of causes, a point that leads Hobbes
on a certain rhetorical flourish: “A wooden Top that is lasht by
the Boyes, and runs about sometimes to one Wall, sometimes to
another, sometimes spinning, sometimes hitting men on the shins, if
it were sensible of its own motion, would think it proceeded from
its own Will, unless it felt what lasht it” (Questions, 41). The notion
of human action as a special kind of event is on this metaphorical
description vividly reduced, as if to suggest that we are little more
than conscious tops, spun by causes beyond our immediate percep-
tion. The metaphor makes two related points, first that autonomy
is a kind of delusion and second that events internal to the mind
follow the same laws of causation as events external to the mind.
Hobbes’s inclusion of mental causation under the same laws as
physical causation serves an important purpose. If the will is locked
to attitudes and attitudes are locked to objects, thoughts, or events,
then human action is subject to the same necessity as everything
else in the world. At the same time, however, this necessity does
not deprive agents of freedom or of responsibility. Here lies one of
Hobbes’s more notable contributions to models of agency in the
early modern and modern periods. Hobbes argues that freedom
requires only that a person is able to act according to her wants,
not that the will is without a determining set of causes. “A free
agent,” on this view, is he “that can do if he will, and forbear if he
will” and liberty the “absence of external impediments” to action
(Questions, 304, 46).16
Freedom turns out to be a particular kind
of causal relation, one in which reasons are able to become actions.
The condition of freedom is therefore satisfied if the reasons one
has proceed uninhibited into the actions one takes. On this account,
no amount of determinacy conflicts with freedom, since the having
of attitudes is what it means to be an agent and since the translat-
ing of attitudes without hindrance into actions is what it means to
have liberty. To put the problem in terms of our earlier example,
it makes no sense to ask whether Hobbes’s will was free to choose
Actions, Agents, Causes
36
going to France but it does to ask whether Hobbes was free to leave
or whether the authorities intercepted his boat. “A Free Agent”
is one “whose motion, or action is not hindered nor stopt. And a
Free Action, that which is produced by a Free Agent” (Questions,
143). The forming of a will to do something, then, is part of the
causal history of an action but alone is neither free nor bound; these
conditions belong only to the agent and action themselves.
What will later be termed compatibilism is a simple yet important
argument: to describe something in terms of its causal history does
nothing to put liberty at risk.17
Rather, it is to take a close look
at that thing and examine its component parts. So to say that a
person acts for a reason is both to explain why actions occur and
to say that a person could not have done otherwise, since doing
otherwise would mean only that she had another will, locked to a
separate series of events. Freedom therefore does not require that I
am set loose from a net of causes; it simply demands that “I can do
if I will,” a condition met by there being no obstacles to my doing.
Hobbes’s compatibilism will (again) have a significant influence on
seventeenth- and eighteenth-century philosophy, from Locke and
Hume, who both embraced it after their own fashions, to Kant,
who found it to be a “wretched subterfuge.”18
If one appeal of the
argument was its sense that actions become intelligible only once we
realize, often against our intuitions, that their sources are extensive,
another is the claim that having reasons for acting takes nothing
away from the accountability one incurs along the way. The contex-
tual sources of action, on Hobbes’s account, bind agents to external
structures, a claim he evidently found convenient in a time of politi-
cal uncertainty. “The necessity of an action doth not make the Laws
that prohibit it unjust,” Hobbes writes in response to Bramhall’s
worry that a commitment to necessity would mean that “praise,
dispraise, reward and punishment are in vain” (Libertie, 27).
Bramhall believes the doctrine of free will is required for systems
of politics and morality to be legitimate, since without it agents
would neither be nor feel accountable for their actions; thus even
Actions, Agents, Causes 37
the “perswasion that there is no true liberty is able to overthrow
all Societies and Commonwealths in the world” (Defence, 91). For
his part, Hobbes finds in necessity the very basis of obedience and
order. Agents come to have intentions, desires, and beliefs because
they witness consequences in the world about them; in this way,
“praise and dispraise, and likewise Reward and Punishment, do by
example make and conform the will to good and evil” (Libertie,
34). This exchange repeats their disagreement over the role of causal
language in the description of actions, this time with reference to
political obligation. Hobbes argues that believing that actions have
consequences is reason, in most cases, to conform one’s behavior
to Scripture and polity, and when it is not, to fear the extraper-
sonal laws of God and the state. The external antecedents to action
turn out to be the very laws one ought to be obeying. From this
perspective, Bramhall’s claim that the will acts on its own discovers
autonomy where there is none and as a result cleaves agents from
their sources of compliance.
	I will come back in subsequent chapters to the seventeenth-century
quarrel over the sources and meanings of actions. Before turning to
the next installment, I want to gather some of the threads of the
controversy as I have reconstructed it so far. Much centered on the
significance of the concept of cause in the description of actions, on
whether cause was essential to understanding connections among
the diverse phenomena of the mind and world or whether it was
a threat to the special nature and place of humans in the cosmos.
Under the rubric of cause, Hobbes and Bramhall disagreed about,
for example, whether persons are endowed with immaterial souls
or whether persons are entirely physical in their composition. As a
corollary to that disagreement, they quarreled over the point where
actions started and stopped—within the precincts of the will or in
attitudes and contexts. Without simplifying too much, then, we
might draw the quarrel over cause into one between an immate-
rialist, dualist, and internalist picture of agency, on the one hand,
and a physicalist, monist, and externalist picture on the other. For
Random documents with unrelated
content Scribd suggests to you:
sniffles, carrying a slate and geography in one hand, and leading a
little sister by the other, who also sniffles and stares. This, too, is
Greater New York, Borough of Richmond, better known as Staten
Island. This borough has nearly all kinds of wild and tame rurality
and suburbanity. Its farms need not be described.
III
Pointing out mere farms in the city becomes rather monotonous;
they are too common. But there is one kind of farm in New York that
is not at all common, that has never existed in any other city, so far
as I know, in ancient or modern times. It is situated, oddly enough,
in about the centre of the 317 square miles of New York—so well as
the centre of a boot-shaped area can be located.
There is profitable oyster-dredging in
several sections of the city.
Cross Thirty-fourth Street Ferry to Long Island City, which really
does not smell so bad as certain of our poets would have us believe;
take the car marked Steinway, and ride for fifteen or twenty
minutes out through dreary city edge, past small, unpainted
manufactories, squalid tenements, dirty backyards, and sad vacant
lots that serve as the last resting-place for decayed trucks and
overworked wagons. Soon after passing a tumble-down windmill,
which looks like an historic old relic, on a hill-top, but which was
built in 1867 and tumbled down only recently, the Steinway Silk Mills
will be reached (they can be distinguished by the long, low wings of
the building covered with windows like a hothouse). Leave the car
here and strike off to the left, down the lane which will soon be an
alley, and then a hundred yards or so from the highway will be seen
the first of the odd, paper-covered houses of a colony of Chinese
farmers who earn their living by tilling the soil of Greater New York.
At short distances are the other huts crouching at the foot of big
trees, with queer gourds hanging out in front to dry, and large
unusual crocks lying about, and huge baskets, and mattings—all
clearly from China; they are as different from what could be bought
on the neighboring avenue as the farm and farmers themselves are
different from most Long Island farms and farmers. Out in the fields,
which are tilled in the Oriental way, utilizing every inch of ground
clean up to the fence, and laid out with even divisions at regular
intervals, like rice-fields, the farmers themselves may be seen,
working with Chinese implements, their pigtails tucked up under
their straw hats, while the western world wags on in its own way all
around them. This is less than five miles from the glass-covered
parade-ground of the Waldorf-Astoria.
They have only three houses among them, that is, there are only
three of these groups of rooms, made of old boards and boxes and
covered with tar paper; but no one in the neighborhood seems to
know just how many Chinamen live there. The same sleeping space
would hold a score or more over in Pell Street.
Being Chinamen, they grow only Chinese produce, a peculiar
kind of bean and some sort of salad, and those large, artistic shaped
melons, seen only in China or Chinatown, which they call something
that sounds like moncha, and which, one of them told me, bring
two cents a pound from the Chinese merchants and restaurateurs of
Manhattan. For my part, I was very glad to learn of these farms, for
I had always been perplexed to account for the fresh salads and
green vegetables, of unmistakably Chinese origin, that can be found
in season in New York's Chinatown. Under an old shed near by they
have their market-wagon, in which, looking inscrutable, they drive
their stuff to market through Long Island City, and by way of James
Slip Ferry over to Chinatown; then back to the farm again, looking
inscrutable. And on Sundays, for all we know, they leave the wagon
behind and go to gamble their earnings away in Mott Street, or
perhaps away over in some of the well-known places of Jersey City.
Then back across the two ferries to farming on dreary Monday
mornings.
IV
Even up in Manhattan there are still places astonishingly unlike
what is expected of the crowded little island on which stands New
York proper. There is Fort Washington with tall trees growing out of
the Revolutionary breastworks, land, under their branches, a fine
view up the Hudson to the mountains—a quiet, sequestered bit of
public park which the public hasn't yet learned to treat as a park,
though within sight of the crowds crossing the viaduct from the
Grant Monument on Riverside. There are wild flowers up there every
spring, and until quite recently so few people visited this spot for
days at a time that there were sometimes woodcock and perhaps
other game in the thickly wooded ravine by the railroad. Soon,
however, the grass on the breastworks will be worn off entirely, and
the aged deaf man who tends the river light on Jeffreys Hook will
become sophisticated, if he is still alive.
Cemetery Ridge, Near Richmond, Staten Island.
It will take longer, however, for the regions to the north, beyond
Washington Heights, down through Inwood and past Tubby Hook, to
look like part of a city. And across the Spuyten Duyvil Creek from
Manhattan Island, up through the winding roads of Riverdale to
Mount St. Vincent, and so across the line to Yonkers, it is still
wooded, comparatively secluded and country-like, even though so
many of the fine country places thereabouts are being deserted.
Over to the eastward, across Broadway, a peaceful road which does
not look like a part of the same thoroughfare as the one with actors
and sky-scrapers upon it, there are the still wilder stretches of
Mosholu and Van Cortlandt Park, where, a year or two ago, large,
well-painted signs on the trees used to say Beware of the
Buffaloes.
A Peaceful Scene in New York.
In the distance is St. Andrew's Church, Borough of Richmond, Staten
Island.
The open country sport of golf has had a good deal to do with
making this rural park more generally appreciated. Golf has done for
Van Cortlandt what the bicycle had done for the Bronx and Pelham
Bay Parks. There are still natural, wild enough looking bits, off from
the beaten paths, in all these parks, scenes that look delightfully
dark and sylvan in the yearly thousands of amateur photographs—
the camera does not show the German family approaching from the
rear, or the egg-shells and broken beer-bottles behind the bushes—
but beware of the police if you break a twig, or pick a blossom.
V
Those who enjoy the study of all the forms of nature except the
highest can find plenty to sigh over in the way the city thrusts itself
upon the country. But to those who think that the haunts and habits
of the Man are not less worthy of observation than those of the
Beaver and the Skunk, it is all rather interesting, and some of it not
so deeply deplorable.
A Relic of the Early Nineteenth Century, Borough of Richmond.
There are certain old country taverns, here and there, up toward
Westchester, and down beyond Brooklyn and over on Staten Island—
not only those which everybody knows, like the Hermitage in the
Bronx and Garrisons over by the fort at Willets Point, but remote
ones which have not yet been exploited in plays or books, and which
still have a fine old flavor, with faded prints of Dexter and Maud S.
and much earlier favorites in the bar-room. In some cases, to be
sure, though still situated at a country cross-roads, with green fields
all about, they are now used for Tammany head-quarters with
pictures of the new candidate for sheriff in the old-fashioned
windows—but most of them would have gone out of existence
entirely after the death of the stage-coach, if it had not been for the
approach of the city, and the side-whiskered New Yorkers of a
previous generation who drove fast horses. If the ghosts of these
men ever drive back to lament the good old days together, they
must be somewhat surprised, possibly disappointed, to find these
rural road-houses doing a better business than even in their day.
The bicycle revived the road-house, and though the bicycle has since
been abandoned by those who prefer fashion to exercise, the places
that the wheel disclosed are not forgotten. They are visited now in
automobiles.
An Old-fashioned Stone-arched Bridge. (Richmond, Staten Island.)
There are all those historic country-houses within the city limits,
well known, and in some cases restored, chiefly by reason of being
within the city, like the Van Cortlandt house, now a part of the park,
and the Jumel mansion standing over Manhattan Field, a house
which gets into most historical novels of New York. Similarly
Claremont Park has adopted the impressive Zabriskie mansion; and
the old Lorillard house in the Bronx might have been torn down by
this time but that it has been made into a park house and
restaurant. Nearly all these are tableted by the patriotic societies,
and made to feel their importance. The Bowne place in Flushing, a
very old type of Long Island farm-house, was turned into a museum
by the Bowne family itself—an excellent idea. The Quaker Meeting-
house in Flushing, though not so old by twenty-five years as it is
painted in the sign which says Built in 1695, will probably be
preserved as a museum too.
An Old House in Flatbush.
Another relic in that locality well worth keeping is the Duryea
place, a striking old stone farm-house with a wide window on the
second floor, now shut in with a wooden cover supported by a long
brace-pole reaching to the ground. Out of this window, it is said, a
cannon used to point. This was while the house was head-quarters
for Hessian officers, during the long monotonous months when the
main army of the British army lay at Flushing from Whitestone to
Jamaica; and upon Flushing Heights there stood one of the tar-
barrel beacons that reached from New York to Norwich Hill, near
Oyster Bay. The British officers used to kill time by playing at Fives
against the blank wall of the Quaker Meeting-house, or by riding
over to Hempstead Plains to the fox-hunts—where the Meadowbrook
Hunt Club rides to the hounds to-day. The common soldiers
meanwhile stayed in Flushing and amused themselves, according to
the same historian, by rolling cannon-balls about a course of nine
holes. That was probably the nearest approach to the great game at
that time in America, and it may have been played on the site of the
present Flushing Golf Club.
These same soldiers also amused themselves in less innocent
ways, so that the Quakers and other non-combatants in and about
this notorious Tory centre used to hide their live stock indoors over
night, to keep it from being made into meals by the British. That
may account for the habit of the family occupying the Duryea place
referred to; they keep their cow in a room at one end of the house.
At any rate it is not necessary for New Yorkers to go to Ireland to
see sights of that sort.
Those are a few of the historic country places that have come to
town. There is a surprisingly large number of them, and even when
they are not adopted and tableted by the D. A. R. or D. R., or S. R.
or S. A. R., they are at least known to local fame, and are pointed
out and made much of.
But the many abandoned country houses which are not
especially historic or significant—except to certain old persons to
whom they once meant home—goodly old places, no longer even
near the country, but caught by the tide well within the city, that is
the kind to be sorry for. Nobody pays much attention to them. A
forlorn For Sale sign hangs out in front, weather-beaten and
discouraged. The tall Colonial columns still try to stand up straight
and to appear unconscious of the faded paint and broken windows,
hoping that no one notices the tangle of weeds in the old-fashioned
garden, where old-fashioned children used to play hide-and-seek
among the box-paths, now overgrown or buried under tin cans....
Across the way, perhaps, there has already squatted an unabashed
row of cheap, vulgar houses, impudent, staring little city homes,
vividly painted, and all exactly alike, with highly ornamented wooden
stoops below and zinc cornices above, like false-hair fronts. They
look at times as though they were putting their heads together to
gossip and smile about their odd, old neighbor that has such out-of-
date fan-lights, that has no electric bell, no folding-beds, and not a
bit of zinc cornicing.
Meanwhile the old house turns its gaze the other way, thinking
of days gone by, patiently waiting the end—which will come soon
enough.
Transcriber's Notes:
Simple typographical errors were corrected.
Punctuation and spelling were made
consistent when a predominant preference was
found in this book; otherwise they were not
changed.
Page 8, first line: manifestations of the spirit
could be or.
*** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK NEW YORK
SKETCHES ***
Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will
be renamed.
Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S.
copyright law means that no one owns a United States copyright in
these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it
in the United States without permission and without paying
copyright royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of
Use part of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG™
concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark,
and may not be used if you charge for an eBook, except by following
the terms of the trademark license, including paying royalties for use
of the Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything
for copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is
very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as
creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research.
Project Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and printed and given
away—you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with
eBooks not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject
to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution.
START: FULL LICENSE
THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK
To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the free
distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or
any other work associated in any way with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg”), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full
Project Gutenberg™ License available with this file or online at
www.gutenberg.org/license.
Section 1. General Terms of Use and
Redistributing Project Gutenberg™
electronic works
1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™
electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree
to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property
(trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all
the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or
destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in your
possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a
Project Gutenberg™ electronic work and you do not agree to be
bound by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund
from the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in
paragraph 1.E.8.
1.B. “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only be
used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people
who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a
few things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg™ electronic
works even without complying with the full terms of this agreement.
See paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with
Project Gutenberg™ electronic works if you follow the terms of this
agreement and help preserve free future access to Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the
Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the
collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the
individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the
United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law
in the United States and you are located in the United States, we do
not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing,
performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the
work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of
course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg™
mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely
sharing Project Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of
this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name associated
with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of this
agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its attached
full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it without charge
with others.
1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also
govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most
countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the
United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the
terms of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying,
performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this
work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes
no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in
any country other than the United States.
1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg:
1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other
immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must
appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg™
work (any work on which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” appears,
or with which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” is associated) is
accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United
States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with
almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away
or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License
included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you
are not located in the United States, you will have to check the
laws of the country where you are located before using this
eBook.
1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is derived
from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not contain a
notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright
holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the
United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are
redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase “Project
Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you must
comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through
1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project
Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted
with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution
must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any
additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms
will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™ License for all works posted
with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning
of this work.
1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project
Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files containing a
part of this work or any other work associated with Project
Gutenberg™.
1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this
electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without
prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1
with active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project
Gutenberg™ License.
1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary,
compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form,
including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you
provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work
in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in
the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website
(www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or
expense to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or
a means of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original
“Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must
include the full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in
paragraph 1.E.1.
1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying,
performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works
unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9.
1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing
access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
provided that:
• You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive
from the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the
method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The
fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark,
but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty
payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on
which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your
periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked
as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation.”
• You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who
notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt
that s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project
Gutenberg™ License. You must require such a user to return or
destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium
and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of
Project Gutenberg™ works.
• You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of
any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in
the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90
days of receipt of the work.
• You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free
distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works.
1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg™
electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set
forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the manager of
the Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set
forth in Section 3 below.
1.F.
1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend
considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe
and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating
the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these efforts, Project
Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the medium on which they may
be stored, may contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to,
incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a
copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or
damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer
codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment.
1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for
the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph 1.F.3,
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the
Project Gutenberg™ trademark, and any other party distributing a
Project Gutenberg™ electronic work under this agreement, disclaim
all liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal
fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR
NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR
BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH
1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK
OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL
NOT BE LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT,
CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF
YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE.
1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you
discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving
it, you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by
sending a written explanation to the person you received the work
from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must
return the medium with your written explanation. The person or
entity that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide
a replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work
electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to
give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in
lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may
demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the
problem.
1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth
in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO
OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF
MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE.
1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied
warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages.
If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the
law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be
interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted
by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any
provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions.
1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation,
the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation,
anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in
accordance with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with
the production, promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg™
electronic works, harmless from all liability, costs and expenses,
including legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of the
following which you do or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or
any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b) alteration, modification, or
additions or deletions to any Project Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any
Defect you cause.
Section 2. Information about the Mission
of Project Gutenberg™
Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of
electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of
computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers.
It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and
donations from people in all walks of life.
Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the
assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s
goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will
remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a
secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg™ and future
generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help,
see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at
www.gutenberg.org.
Section 3. Information about the Project
Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation
The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-profit
501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the
state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal
Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification
number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg
Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent
permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws.
The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500 West,
Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up
to date contact information can be found at the Foundation’s website
and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact
Section 4. Information about Donations to
the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive
Foundation
Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without
widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission of
increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can
be freely distributed in machine-readable form accessible by the
widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many
small donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to
maintaining tax exempt status with the IRS.
The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating
charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United
States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a
considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and
keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in
locations where we have not received written confirmation of
compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of
compliance for any particular state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate.
While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where
we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no
prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in
such states who approach us with offers to donate.
International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make
any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from
outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff.
Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation
methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of
other ways including checks, online payments and credit card
donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate.
Section 5. General Information About
Project Gutenberg™ electronic works
Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project
Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could be
freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and
distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose network of
volunteer support.
Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed
editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in
the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not
necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper
edition.
Most people start at our website which has the main PG search
facility: www.gutenberg.org.
This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™,
including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary
Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how
to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.
Welcome to our website – the perfect destination for book lovers and
knowledge seekers. We believe that every book holds a new world,
offering opportunities for learning, discovery, and personal growth.
That’s why we are dedicated to bringing you a diverse collection of
books, ranging from classic literature and specialized publications to
self-development guides and children's books.
More than just a book-buying platform, we strive to be a bridge
connecting you with timeless cultural and intellectual values. With an
elegant, user-friendly interface and a smart search system, you can
quickly find the books that best suit your interests. Additionally,
our special promotions and home delivery services help you save time
and fully enjoy the joy of reading.
Join us on a journey of knowledge exploration, passion nurturing, and
personal growth every day!
ebookbell.com

More Related Content

PDF
Just Property Volume Three Property In An Age Of Ideologies Christopher Pierson
PDF
In Search Of The Whole Twelve Essays On Faith And Academic Life Original John...
PDF
Contentious Minds How Talk And Ties Sustain Activism Florence Passy
PDF
Social Epistemology Adrian Haddock Alan Millar Duncan Pritchard Editor
PDF
Responsibility The Epistemic Condition First Edition Philip Robichaud
PDF
The Ascent Of Affect Genealogy And Critique Ruth Leys
PDF
Rightness And Reasons Interpretation In Cultural Practices Michael Krausz
DOCX
Chapter 1What is theoryIn literary and cultural studies.docx
Just Property Volume Three Property In An Age Of Ideologies Christopher Pierson
In Search Of The Whole Twelve Essays On Faith And Academic Life Original John...
Contentious Minds How Talk And Ties Sustain Activism Florence Passy
Social Epistemology Adrian Haddock Alan Millar Duncan Pritchard Editor
Responsibility The Epistemic Condition First Edition Philip Robichaud
The Ascent Of Affect Genealogy And Critique Ruth Leys
Rightness And Reasons Interpretation In Cultural Practices Michael Krausz
Chapter 1What is theoryIn literary and cultural studies.docx

Similar to Actions And Objects From Hobbes To Richardson Jonathan Kramnick (20)

PDF
Essay Writing On School. Argumentative Essay.docx Higher Education Governme...
PDF
Intuition Imagination And Philosophical Methodology Tamar Szabo Gendler
PDF
Resisting Ethics First Edition Scott Schaffer
PDF
Spinoza And The Politics Of Renaturalization Hasana Sharp
PDF
Realism And Antirealism William P Alston Ed
PDF
Skepticism And Freedom 1st Edition Richard A Epstein
PDF
Radical Cosmopolitics The Ethics And Politics Of Democratic Universalism Jame...
PDF
Confronting Theory The Psychology Of Cultural Studies Philip Bell
PDF
The Familial State Ruling Families And Merchant Capitalism In Early Modern Eu...
PDF
Undisciplining Knowledge Interdisciplinarity In The Twentieth Century Harvey ...
PDF
Science Truth And Democracy Oxford University Press Kitcher
PPTX
St Deiniols
PDF
Mind Body Motion Matter Eighteenthcentury British And French Literary Perspec...
PDF
Essays On Nonconceptual Content York H Gunther York Gunther
PDF
Toleration Diversity And Global Justice Kokchor Tan
PDF
Intangible Materialism The Body Scientific Knowledge And The Power Of Languag...
PDF
Intangible Materialism The Body Scientific Knowledge And The Power Of Languag...
PDF
The Time Of Popular Sovereignty Process And The Democratic State 1st Edition ...
PDF
Science As Social Knowledge Values And Objectivity In Scientific Inquiry Hele...
PDF
A Brief Illustrated History Of Romanians Neagu Djuvara
Essay Writing On School. Argumentative Essay.docx Higher Education Governme...
Intuition Imagination And Philosophical Methodology Tamar Szabo Gendler
Resisting Ethics First Edition Scott Schaffer
Spinoza And The Politics Of Renaturalization Hasana Sharp
Realism And Antirealism William P Alston Ed
Skepticism And Freedom 1st Edition Richard A Epstein
Radical Cosmopolitics The Ethics And Politics Of Democratic Universalism Jame...
Confronting Theory The Psychology Of Cultural Studies Philip Bell
The Familial State Ruling Families And Merchant Capitalism In Early Modern Eu...
Undisciplining Knowledge Interdisciplinarity In The Twentieth Century Harvey ...
Science Truth And Democracy Oxford University Press Kitcher
St Deiniols
Mind Body Motion Matter Eighteenthcentury British And French Literary Perspec...
Essays On Nonconceptual Content York H Gunther York Gunther
Toleration Diversity And Global Justice Kokchor Tan
Intangible Materialism The Body Scientific Knowledge And The Power Of Languag...
Intangible Materialism The Body Scientific Knowledge And The Power Of Languag...
The Time Of Popular Sovereignty Process And The Democratic State 1st Edition ...
Science As Social Knowledge Values And Objectivity In Scientific Inquiry Hele...
A Brief Illustrated History Of Romanians Neagu Djuvara
Ad

Recently uploaded (20)

PDF
BP 704 T. NOVEL DRUG DELIVERY SYSTEMS (UNIT 1)
PPTX
ELIAS-SEZIURE AND EPilepsy semmioan session.pptx
DOC
Soft-furnishing-By-Architect-A.F.M.Mohiuddin-Akhand.doc
PDF
BP 704 T. NOVEL DRUG DELIVERY SYSTEMS (UNIT 2).pdf
PDF
FORM 1 BIOLOGY MIND MAPS and their schemes
PPTX
Virtual and Augmented Reality in Current Scenario
PPTX
CHAPTER IV. MAN AND BIOSPHERE AND ITS TOTALITY.pptx
PDF
My India Quiz Book_20210205121199924.pdf
PPTX
Chinmaya Tiranga Azadi Quiz (Class 7-8 )
PDF
LDMMIA Reiki Yoga Finals Review Spring Summer
PPTX
Onco Emergencies - Spinal cord compression Superior vena cava syndrome Febr...
PPTX
History, Philosophy and sociology of education (1).pptx
PPTX
TNA_Presentation-1-Final(SAVE)) (1).pptx
PPTX
Introduction to pro and eukaryotes and differences.pptx
PDF
IGGE1 Understanding the Self1234567891011
PDF
David L Page_DCI Research Study Journey_how Methodology can inform one's prac...
PPTX
B.Sc. DS Unit 2 Software Engineering.pptx
PPTX
20th Century Theater, Methods, History.pptx
PDF
Chinmaya Tiranga quiz Grand Finale.pdf
PDF
Empowerment Technology for Senior High School Guide
BP 704 T. NOVEL DRUG DELIVERY SYSTEMS (UNIT 1)
ELIAS-SEZIURE AND EPilepsy semmioan session.pptx
Soft-furnishing-By-Architect-A.F.M.Mohiuddin-Akhand.doc
BP 704 T. NOVEL DRUG DELIVERY SYSTEMS (UNIT 2).pdf
FORM 1 BIOLOGY MIND MAPS and their schemes
Virtual and Augmented Reality in Current Scenario
CHAPTER IV. MAN AND BIOSPHERE AND ITS TOTALITY.pptx
My India Quiz Book_20210205121199924.pdf
Chinmaya Tiranga Azadi Quiz (Class 7-8 )
LDMMIA Reiki Yoga Finals Review Spring Summer
Onco Emergencies - Spinal cord compression Superior vena cava syndrome Febr...
History, Philosophy and sociology of education (1).pptx
TNA_Presentation-1-Final(SAVE)) (1).pptx
Introduction to pro and eukaryotes and differences.pptx
IGGE1 Understanding the Self1234567891011
David L Page_DCI Research Study Journey_how Methodology can inform one's prac...
B.Sc. DS Unit 2 Software Engineering.pptx
20th Century Theater, Methods, History.pptx
Chinmaya Tiranga quiz Grand Finale.pdf
Empowerment Technology for Senior High School Guide
Ad

Actions And Objects From Hobbes To Richardson Jonathan Kramnick

  • 1. Actions And Objects From Hobbes To Richardson Jonathan Kramnick download https://ebookbell.com/product/actions-and-objects-from-hobbes-to- richardson-jonathan-kramnick-1894112 Explore and download more ebooks at ebookbell.com
  • 2. Here are some recommended products that we believe you will be interested in. You can click the link to download. Actions And Objects From Hobbes To Richardson Jonathan Kramnick https://ebookbell.com/product/actions-and-objects-from-hobbes-to- richardson-jonathan-kramnick-51932354 Making Objects And Events A Hylomorphic Theory Of Artifacts Actions And Organisms 1st Edition Simon J Evnine https://ebookbell.com/product/making-objects-and-events-a-hylomorphic- theory-of-artifacts-actions-and-organisms-1st-edition-simon-j- evnine-5772442 Object Recognition Attention And Action 1st Edition Ingo Rentschler https://ebookbell.com/product/object-recognition-attention-and- action-1st-edition-ingo-rentschler-4405686 Actions And Invariants Of Algebraic Groups Second Edition Second Edition Walter Ricardo Ferrer Santos https://ebookbell.com/product/actions-and-invariants-of-algebraic- groups-second-edition-second-edition-walter-ricardo-ferrer- santos-6837258
  • 3. Actions And Invariants Of Algebraic Groups 1st Edition Walter Ferrer Santos https://ebookbell.com/product/actions-and-invariants-of-algebraic- groups-1st-edition-walter-ferrer-santos-882248 Actions And Reactions Kipling Rudyard https://ebookbell.com/product/actions-and-reactions-kipling- rudyard-3890468 Torus Actions And Their Applications In Topology And Combinatorics Victor M Buchstaber And Taras E Panov https://ebookbell.com/product/torus-actions-and-their-applications-in- topology-and-combinatorics-victor-m-buchstaber-and-taras-e- panov-5250074 Criminal Actions And Social Situations Understanding The Role Of Structure And Intentionality 1st Edition Anthony Amatrudo Auth https://ebookbell.com/product/criminal-actions-and-social-situations- understanding-the-role-of-structure-and-intentionality-1st-edition- anthony-amatrudo-auth-6844794 Nimesulide Actions And Uses 1st Edition Kim D Rainsford Editor https://ebookbell.com/product/nimesulide-actions-and-uses-1st-edition- kim-d-rainsford-editor-1819566
  • 6. Actions and Objects from Hobbes to Richardson
  • 8. Actions and Objects from Hobbes to Richardson Jonathan Kramnick stanford university press Stanford, California
  • 9. Stanford University Press Stanford, California ©2010 by the Board of Trustees of the Leland Stanford Junior University No part of this book may be reproduced or transmitted in any form or by any means, electronic or mechanical, including photocopying and recording, or in any information storage or retrieval system without the prior written permission of Stanford University Press. Library of Congress Cataloging-in-Publication Data Kramnick, Jonathan Brody.    Actions and objects from Hobbes to Richardson / Jonathan Kramnick.       p. cm.   Includes bibliographical references and index.    isbn 978-0-8047-7051-4 (cloth : alk. paper) —    isbn 978-0-8047-7052-1 (pbk. : alk. paper)    1. English literature—18th century—History and criticism. 2. English literature—Early modern, 1500–1700—History and criticism. 3. Act (Philosophy) in literature. 4. Philosophy of mind in literature. 5. Causation in literature. 6. Philosophy, English— 17th century. 7. Philosophy, English—18th century. I. Title. pr448.p5k73 2010 820.9'384—dc22       2010010565 Printed in the United States of America on acid-free, archival-quality paper Typeset at Stanford University Press in 10.75/15 Sabon
  • 10. Contents Preface    vii Introduction: Nothing from Nothing    1 1. Actions, Agents, Causes    27 2. Consciousness and Mental Causation: Lucretius, Rochester, Locke    61 3. Rochester’s Mind    99 4. Uneasiness, or Locke among Others    141 5. Haywood and Consent    168 6. Action and Inaction in Samuel Richardson’s Clarissa    194 Notes    233 Index    299
  • 12. Preface This book is about the literature and philosophy of action during the last half of the seventeenth and first half of the eighteenth cen- tury, the period that begins roughly with Hobbes and Rochester and ends roughly with Hume and Richardson. It features works that examine what happens when someone acts, when someone writes a letter or lifts her feet or kills or kisses, and so on. For many, the difference between actions and other kinds of events turned on the presence of mental states. Someone writes a letter because she wants to communicate information and intends for her reader to under- stand her. Her desire for the one or intention for the other causes physical movements of various kinds. And yet how does a mental state like desire or intention cause the body to move? This simple question was of vast significance for all kinds of writers during the period, and opened up literary and philosophical problems for our time as well as theirs, from how a work of writing can represent thought on the page, to how matter can be the locus of conscious- ness, to whether minds actually cause anything to happen after all. Writing about the mind during the period took many forms and has been the topic of much important work in literary and intel- lectual history. The relation between mind and actions, however, remains relatively untapped and points in a number of unusual directions. For example, although this book is above all interested in the language of mental states, it does not make an argument about the growth of inwardness or interiority or the psychological subject during the period. Rather, considering actions leads in a different
  • 13. Preface viii direction. Minds were understood to do many kinds of things— from represent objects, to work through equations, to grieve—but when they caused someone to act, they were understood to blend in some fashion with the rest of the world. For some, this kind of causal relation meant that minds were at bottom like everything else in nature. When these writers considered actions, they were often led to unexpected or unsettling conclusions: that the will might not be free, that all matter might be sentient or nothing sentient at all, that states of mind extend outside the head. For others, the topic of actions provided an occasion to block just these sorts of conclusions and to distinguish the place of mind and mental causes from other parts of the world. The late seventeenth and early eighteenth century was indeed a lively time for the consideration of actions, with the combined emergence of empirical philosophies of mind and new literary forms designed to feature experience in often startling ways. Against this expansive backdrop, I follow the problem of actions from the cul- tures of Restoration-era science to mid-eighteenth-century social theory, from worries about political authority to the consideration of a commercial society. While I place importance on what we might call externalism, I also watch notions of the external shift from physical bits of matter in motion to the elaborate networks of law and exchange. My goal has not been to follow a single perspec- tive as it grows to dominance, however, but rather to examine com- peting models of mind and action across the period and into ours. I thus examine writers who have been integral for literary studies along with those whose ideas might challenge our expectations on a number of topics: from where seventeenth- and eighteenth-century writers looked to find the sources of actions to what kinds of enti- ties they considered to be conscious. Actions and Objects has been generously supported through- out by Rutgers University. In the early stages, I received fellowship help from the NEH, the William Andrews Clark Memorial Library, and the Huntington Library. At the end, I was the beneficiary of a
  • 14. Preface ix wonderful year at the Stanford Humanities Center, which saw the completion of this manuscript and the start of another. As I tried out some of these arguments and readings, a few appeared in print. Early versions of sections of Chapters 3 and 5 appeared in ELH and a very different version of a section of Chapter 4 in the Yale Jour- nal of Criticism. They have now been completely reconsidered and rewritten, but trace sentences remain. One pleasure of taking some time to finish is accumulating so many debts of gratitude. I’ve been extremely fortunate to test some of these arguments among a superlative group of graduate students over the years. I could simply not have written a word without their questions, responses, and quarrels. My period cohort—Lynn Festa, Paula McDowell, and Michael McKeon—has provided invaluable feedback and conversation. Also at Rutgers, I’ve had the pleasure of working with Billy Galperin, Colin Jager, Meredith McGill, Jonah Siegel, Henry Turner, and Rebecca Walkowitz. The “Mind and Cul- ture” seminar at the Center for Cultural Analysis provided a burst of intellectual energy and renewal just when I needed it most; our many guests and fellows will find their promptings and ideas scat- tered over these pages. The same is true for the crew at Stanford, old friends and new: John Bender, Terry Castle, Denise Gigante, Joshua Landy, and Blakey Vermeule. It has come to seem that the broader eighteenth- century world is an expansive set of fascinating interlocutors, including Helen Deutsch, Sarah Ellenzweig, Marcie Frank, Jody Greene, Sandra Macpherson, John Richetti, Helen Thompson, and others who have listened to me talk about actions and minds over the years and who have helped to shape the argument in ways they might not realize. Parts of this book were delivered to audiences at Berkeley, Johns Hopkins, Princeton, Rice, Stanford, UCLA, the University of Chicago, and Yale, where audiences were curious and receptive and challenging in the best ways. James Kierstead, Mike Gavin, and my editor Emily-Jane Cohen all made it possible for this book to come together in the end.
  • 15. Preface It gives me great pleasure finally to thank those whose contin- ued intellectual presence in my life I consider a tremendous gift: Jared Gardner, Elizabeth Hewitt, Jonathan Goldberg, Adela Pinch, Michael Trask, Michael Warner, and Bliss Kern. Bliss read the entire book and made it better.
  • 16. Actions and Objects from Hobbes to Richardson
  • 18. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing Things happen. Often we try to explain them. When Edmond Halley looked back on records of passing comets, he noticed that one seemed to appear every seventy-six years. He then thought hard about orbital velocity and gravity, drawing on what he knew about mathematics and physics. When a fashionable young man cut off a lock of hair belonging to a fashionable young woman, Alexan- der Pope wrote a poem. He thought hard about human actions, drawing on what he knew about motivation and desire. Halley and Pope both understood that neither comets nor cuttings come into the universe from nothing. Yet for Halley, the comet’s return didn’t have anything to do with beliefs or decisions. The comet didn’t choose to shoot by earth. Rather, its particular mass and distance from the sun put it on an unalterable ellipse. For Pope, the cutting of the lock had little to do with the properties of metal shears or strands of hair. The Baron chose to cut Belinda’s hair. Pope would like to know why he did so: Say what strange Motive, Goddess! cou’d compel A well-bred Lord t’assault a gentle Belle? Oh say what stranger Cause, yet unexplor’d, Cou’d make a gentle Belle reject a Lord?1 Were we to examine the Baron’s motives, Pope says, we might discover why he cut Belinda’s hair. Were we to examine hers, we might discover why she rejected his advances. Were we to do either, we would learn how motives serve as causes, “am’rous Causes” to be exact. Enclosed in the two couplets therefore is an implicit theory.
  • 19. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing Belinda and the Baron are agents. Their actions have causes. Among these causes are states of mind. We may go even further. States of mind distinguish actions like the rape of the lock from events like the appearance of Halley’s comet.2 They do so because they serve a causal role. States of mind make something happen, just like states of physical matter. In other words, Pope plucks minds from other kinds of things only to make us wonder how far the distinction goes. This book is about minds and actions in Restoration and eighteenth-century Britain. It examines how writers described what precedes and constitutes an agent’s doing something, whether writing a letter or fleeing a kingdom. The topic gathered new attention during the period because it opened the possibility for a causal theory of behavior in line with causal theories applied elsewhere in the natural world. If desires, fears, beliefs, and so on were like causes and actions were like effects, some said, then minds were similar to other things in the environment; if minds represent the world in motion, others responded, they were in some special sense distinct from everything else. The discussion animated genres as diverse as the treatise, the lyric, and the novel. Sometimes it concerned matters as ordinary as the lifting of one’s feet; other times it engaged topics as broad as what it means to be a person. In each case, the concern was how states of mind might prompt, accompany, or follow the movement of physical bodies. In this introduction, I will set out the conceptual issues involved in the period’s consideration of actions. I’ll then turn to a chapter-by-chapter summary of my argument. If my sense of this book is right, several of my formulations may be surprising, so I’ll present them in some detail. One might expect a book about minds to validate the long- standing sense that the eighteenth century witnesses a new language of inwardness or subjectivity associated with the joint rise of empiri- cal philosophy and the novel.3 I complicate this thesis by pointing to the largely unacknowledged role of external factors in the period’s conception of mind. In the works I examine, the distinguishing
  • 20. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing feature of minds is the causal role they do or do not play in physical movement. So while the writers I feature develop techniques to show minds at work, their goal is to describe why certain actions occur and how mental states fit into the rest of the world. The ostensible privacy or interiority of mental states is often not an issue. We may think of this as an important property of actions. Actions extend mind into the world. Belinda might conceivably be thinking about all sorts of things in the course of her day, from the taste of tea to troubles with Betty. Pope is interested in why she rejected the Baron, however, and so therefore looks at her reasons for doing so. The same might be said for many of the well-known and incidental actions mulled over in the writing of the period. Why did Evelina accept Orville’s invitation to dance? Why did Moll steal that bundle? Any time a writer asks why such an event happened, she pares mental states into those fixed to behavior, the desires or beliefs that form reasons for acting. To the degree to which literary history has focused on inwardness or privacy, therefore, it has missed several important features of mind-talk during the long eighteenth century. This book looks closely at three such features as they take the form of nagging questions: Are actions freely chosen or subject to necessity? How do mental properties cause physical change? How can a physical object be the locus of conscious experience? Let’s start with the first question. The notion that human behavior might be discussed in causal terms brought with it a serious entail- ment. As soon as we know all the facts about Halley’s comet, we understand why it has to appear every seventy-six years. The comet doesn’t have any say in the matter. An inflexible confluence of causes (mass, gravity, velocity, and so forth) rigidly determines its arrival. The comet is subject to necessity. The question thus emerges with some urgency if the same is true for actions. Were we to know all the facts about the Baron’s cutting of the lock, or Belinda’s refusal of the Baron, would we understand why each had to happen? Pope’s language of causes suggests this may be so. Indeed, John Dennis voices precisely this worry in his Remarks on Mr. Pope’s Rape of
  • 21. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing the Lock (1728), in which he complains that the word “compel” in line six “is a Botch for the Sake of the Rhyme,” because it “supposes the Baron to be a Beast, and not a free Agent.”4 Although he is no friend to Pope, Dennis would still like to save the poet from the charge of determinism. Surely Pope didn’t mean to say that the Baron lacked freedom of the will. Pope’s emphasis on causation suggests that Dennis was wrong. The poor Baron may have been just as compelled as the comet, unable to do anything other than cut. He too may have been subject to necessity.5 Writers like Dennis worry that necessity is a sort of alibi for reprehensible behavior. Don’t punish me, the Baron might say; I couldn’t have done otherwise. The assumption is that if one isn’t free to choose one’s actions then one can’t really be held responsible for them. The freedom that allows agents to take responsibility for what they do is, on this view, incompatible with the necessity that says they could never have done otherwise. One major contribu- tion of seventeenth- and eighteenth-century theories of action was, however, precisely not to pose freedom and responsibility against necessity. It was rather to show how the two could be compatible. Traditionally credited to Hobbes, compatibilism of this kind has had great influence up to the present day.6 The argument works by a series of redefinitions. First among them is freedom itself. “Liberty or Freedome,” Hobbes writes, “signifieth (properly) the absence of Opposition” or “externall Impediments of motion.”7 On this view, freedom does not refer to an ability to choose or will actions. Rather, freedom refers to an ability to perform actions once they are chosen. While “no Liberty can be inferred of the will, desire, or inclination,” we can infer a “Liberty of the man; which consisteth in this, that he finds no stop, in doing what he has the will, desire, or inclination to doe” (146). A will may no more be free than a thought may be brittle or a square may be fast. In contrast, an action is free when it may be brought to completion, confined when it is impeded. This redefinition was useful for Hobbes because it put the freedom of actions together with the safety provided by the state. Absolute
  • 22. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing power was not a threat to liberty; rather, it provided the protection for agents to act as they would choose.8 Despite changes in political theory over the course of the period, the idea that freedom could be compatible with necessity had considerable endurance. Hume for example defined liberty as “a power of acting or not acting, accord- ing to the determinations of the will” and then argued that this power in no way conflicted with universal causation: “We cannot surely mean, that actions have so little connexion with motives, inclinations, and circumstances, that one does not follow with a certain degree of uniformity from the other, and that one affords no inference by which we can conclude the existence of the other.”9 Surely, he says, we cannot imagine that the will is indifferent to motives or that motives don’t serve as causes. Liberty requires only that actions may be completed. For Hobbes, the state performs this role by allowing for common safety and enduring contracts; for Hume a society of commerce and reciprocity draws the behavior of one person to the interests of another. In either case, the will finds its place in a lattice of causes, and actions come under the same fine- grained analysis as the rest of nature. Although the compatibilist account of agency looms large in the history of philosophy, with canonical British writers like Hobbes, Locke, and Hume at front and center, its importance for questions of literary history has not been much explored. One goal of this book is to do just that. The topic of reasons for acting might be of interest for how we think about such things as the writing of literary character and the placing of actions into narratives.10 Compatibil- ism in turn might be of help to refining our sense of how dependent characterization was on notions of internal psychology and how far it extended outward into external objects and events. I mentioned earlier, for example, that talk about actions brought mental causes into the world rather than separating them from it. I would add to this thesis that compatibilism brought the world into the mind. As a matter of definition, no cause ever exists on its own. Causes are paired to effects and, presumably, caused by something else too.
  • 23. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing With respect to mental states, this means that reasons for acting extend from experiences or desires or intentions to external objects and back. It is not so hard to see how reasons might be internal. The Baron desires that Belinda’s hair be cut. Belinda hopes for the Baron to go away. While the lock and the Baron exist independently of the mind, each is at the same time an object of a propositional statement. They change according to the presiding mental verb (or attitude, as we would now say): the lock is cut in the first case, the Baron ushered away in the second.11 Mental states are thus able to bear content, like a lock of hair, and mediate behavior, like closing a pair of scissors.12 It is perhaps not quite so easy to see how these same states might reach beyond the person. No small part of my argument, however, will depend on the period’s sense of this possibility. In different ways, Hobbes and Hume both say that every event or object or idea links to another in a long chain of causation. There is no way to view any one precisely on its own, since each has antecedents and effects. With respect to mental states, the result of this intuition is that ideas and intentions ultimately make their way to the social and physical environment. When this relation tightens some, the social or physical hookup actually plays a causal role in this or that action. In our present example, we need only look at the system of external rules and meanings that jointly govern the behavior of the Baron or Belinda. “Am’rous Causes” reach through things like cards and hair and forms like courtship and epic. I will be interested in accounts of actions that stress the connec- tion between subjective experience and the environment or that show how the meaning of concepts is fixed on the outside or that tie volitional states like desire or intention to physical states like the movement of particles. I will argue in other words for the importance of what I’ll call externalism in the literature and philos- ophy of the period.13 In many of the cases I look at, the emphasis fell on causation as the means by which mental states or proper- ties have at once a real existence and are looped into other things. Even as causation promised to join mind to the world, however, the
  • 24. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing precise relation between the two became subject to some worry. The question here—the second on my earlier list—was whether mental states instigate physical change. One might be surprised if they didn’t.14 Pope’s question about the Baron would only make sense, after all, were his motives able to bring about his cuttings. Yet for all the apparent simplicity of this sort of episode, it became clear to a variety of writers that the process was difficult to pin down. Here are Locke’s droll comments on the matter: My right Hand writes, whilst my left Hand is still: What causes rest in one, and motion in the other? Nothing but my Will,—a Thought of my Mind; my Thought only changing, the right Hand rests, and the left Hand moves. This is matter of fact, which cannot be denied: Explain this, and make it intelligible, and then the next step will be to understand Creation.15 Locke’s hand has been writing for some time. It has been forming letters from ink, words from letters, sentences from words, and paragraphs from sentences. The paragraphs read as more than accidents. They make a certain sense and so seem to be the product of an intending agent. Try as he might, however, Locke cannot exactly describe how his will executes the writing. (I can’t either. I’m telling myself to type this on the keyboard. So far my fingers are moving as I’d like them to. How and why are beyond me.) Locke does not dismiss the efficacy of mental properties or consign them to a separate kind of substance.16 Rather, he considers the causal relation between will and writing to be “a matter of fact” and to be an example of a kind of relation that underpins every single act done with deliberate intention. His amused caution has to do with figuring out how the pieces of the causal puzzle fit into each other. Does the relation between will and hand-movement have the same features as the one between, say, heat and the evaporation of water? The evaporation of water from heat happens every time the tempera- ture crosses a certain threshold. The turning of letters into words happens by fits and starts, according to a will described as a distinc-
  • 25. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing tively mental property. Locke is therefore sure of two things: that he experiences the decision to move one hand and then the other, and that his experience causes the movement of his hands. There is something that it feels like for him to will hand movement. There is nothing that it feels like for heat to evaporate water. In the face of this sort of relation, however, Locke (as it were) throws up his hands. He knows it exists yet cannot provide an intelligible description of how it happens. Analytic philosophers would call this a problem of mental causation.17 It is essential to every chapter of the book. Mental causation is so important because without it there would be no concept of agency and no description of actions, only events. It is important because the scene that Locke provides an expository accounting of here reappears in different guises across the litera- tures of the period, from the search into the “am’rous Causes” beneath and before the rape of the lock to the prolonged question- ing of the motives of a character like Clarissa Harlowe in doing things like writing to Lovelace and leaving her family home. It is important finally because of the very bafflement Locke so limpidly voices. Attempts to resolve the problem of mental causation came in a variety of forms: from the idea that mental states or properties might have no causal role to play—epiphenomenalism as it is now called—to the notion that external objects and events do the causing for us; from accounts of the mind’s free and independent force on the material world to a recognition that causal relations are best inferred from an outsider’s stance. The pleasure in considering this problem over the course of the seventeenth and eighteenth centuries has not, however, been in watching a single answer take shape from the various responses. It has been rather in following the arguments as they take off from their several sources, from Hobbes to Hume, Rochester to Richardson, and in between. At the heart of the problem of mental causation is the distinction, if there is one, between mind and matter. For most of the writers I consider, the causal relation at issue is not one between two kinds of substance. For some the distinction is between mental and physical
  • 26. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing description, with the underlying substance question ruled out by metaphysical fiat; for others the problem is fitting the mind into a world that is wholly material; for still others a ghost does in fact haunt the machine. The concerns raised by these responses take me to the last of the three questions I raised earlier. Were we to ask who cut Belinda’s hair we would think it odd if someone were to reply the scissors. Why would we think so? On a first pass, we might say because the Baron is a person and the scissors an object. We might then hang a series of further distinctions on this difference. Persons have a kind of value and set of rights, for example, while objects do not. Junk the Baron’s scissors and he might be annoyed, but you’re unlikely to be arrested. Drown the Baron in the Thames and you might be held accountable for a crime. The concept of person is, as Locke will say, a “forensic category,” useful for the assigning of blame or praise, reward or punishment.18 But to say that persons cause things to happen and objects do not is to take as a premise the difference in roles one is trying to explain. Why then do we say that a person has causal powers while a pair of scissors does not? For many during the period the answer was that persons have conscious experience.19 There is something that it is like to be the Baron.20 There is nothing that it is like to be a pair of scissors. Here we can perhaps take matters no further. A person is a kind of thing that is conscious; a pair of scissors is a kind of thing that is not. Full stop. The premise of this sort of argument is actually twofold. It says that persons have consciousness and that consciousness distinguishes one person from another. This claim is made with tremendous influence in chapter 27 of Locke’s Essay Concern- ing Human Understanding (1690). For Locke and others, talk of consciousness was hard to have without talk of personal identity, and likewise bringing up personal identity was hard to do without having something to say about consciousness. One linked series of conscious moments wraps the whole into a single entity, making (as the case may be) the young Locke an identical person to the old one. If consciousness and personhood go together, however, they do
  • 27. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 10 so with some interesting points of tension. For some writers, includ- ing Locke on occasion, consciousness was something that bodies have and do. It was not a separate substance put into them. But how can a physical system be the locus of experience? Matter seems by definition to be without experience, yet put together in certain ways it gives rise to sentience, awareness, pleasure, pain, appetites, and the like. In contemporary work on the mind, the question of how this is possible is known as “the hard problem of conscious- ness,” and it remains decisively unanswered to this day.21 Following a single thread in the treatment of actions has thus backed me into a large area of concern, one that I try to keep tightly laced to reasons for acting. This topic includes consciousness because it is conscious objects that would seem to have reasons. How precisely that is so, however, does take us into really interesting and difficult issues. One such issue comes directly out of the seventeenth and eighteenth century’s version of today’s “hard problem.” It went something like this: assuming that material entities are able to have the sort of experiences that lead to actions—conscious reasons for acting, let’s say—why are some entities conscious and others not? At bottom, there is little difference between the Baron and the scissors (or the comet). Each is a composite of particles. Yet Baron- particles give rise to consciousness and scissor-particles do not. In the chapters that follow, I will look at a few works that directly ask why that is so. Once again, my interest is not only with period- defining answers but also with some difficulties encountered along the way. I am especially drawn to texts that come at problems of consciousness from an oblique angle or that offer radical or at least off-center responses to the problems at hand. I’ll be interested in texts that try to bring consciousness and personhood together, but I will also be interested in those that pry them apart, that present conscious experiences without a person having them or persons without conscious experiences in train. I’ll be interested, finally, in texts willing to follow their premises to seemingly unusual conclu- sions, such as all things having some sort of consciousness or (conversely) nothing having consciousness at all.
  • 28. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 11 Keeping an eye toward the unexpected conclusion has provided one way to narrow a path through a topic as broad as the literature and philosophy of actions. It is also, I think, what happens when you watch writers wrestle with nearly intractable quandaries: An action is the kind of event whose cause includes mental states, but what, after all, does “whose cause includes” really mean? A person is the kind of entity that has consciousness, but how and why is that so? Answer me these and perhaps you will, as Locke says, explain creation. Two guiding principles are at issue here. Questions of agency and consciousness have long concerned literary study in general and the study of Restoration and eighteenth-century litera- ture in particular. I attempt to look closely at the component parts of one critical feature of this concern: how reasons, intentions, and other states of mind do or do not serve as causes for acting. This feature then opens up a number of related topics about minds and persons and contexts for acting. The principle is to engage large, period-defining concepts of character or consciousness, such as they are, through incremental examples and debates. The second princi- ple reflects somewhat on the first. I am inclined to tilt the applecart rather than hold it in place. So where the predominant model has favored the growth of inwardness, sympathy, and subjectivity, I tend (again) to favor things external, like the elemental parts of matter or the chains of causes or the forms of contract. With the exception of the first chapter, this book moves freely between what in retrospect we would call philosophical and literary writing.22 I take great pleasure in the nonexistence of this distinction in the eighteenth century, a period when David Hume could say his ruling passion was a “love of literary fame” and Samuel Richardson could say that he wrote “instantaneous Descriptions and Reflec- tions” of minds and hearts at work. I view this overlap of concerns as permission to stipulate a relation between texts that have grown to seem far-flung. I do track allusion, citation, and debate, but in the main my method has been to follow the appearance and movement of problems, especially those concerning the antecedents to actions and the ontology of persons and objects. These topics
  • 29. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 12 obey no boundaries of genre, though they are framed in different ways according to the formal properties and needs of the texts in which they come into view. So, for example, an epistolary novel might choose to distribute its account of causes between writers of letters, while a third-person fiction might try to represent a charac- ter’s reasons or intentions; a piece of discursive prose might develop a theory in explicit conversation with antagonists while a court satire might make such dialogue internal to its lines. I arrange this movement into a loose chronology: from a new attention to actions amid dynastic anxieties and civil war to a concern with minds and behavior amid polite and commercial exchange. With this backdrop in place, it has been on occasion important to put the texts slightly out of sequence or to put some writers in more than one chapter. I do this to draw out concepts that might otherwise be obscured by a stricter sense of order. I don’t think that much is lost in histori- cal presentation by doing so; but the alternative would, I believe, make topics like mental causation and consciousness a little more difficult to track. These topics are of intense interest for Restora- tion and eighteenth-century writers. At the same time, they have been subject to concentrated attention in contemporary philosophy of mind and cognitive science. While I focus on Restoration and eighteenth-century texts, therefore, I also draw now and again on the persistence of these concerns into our time. Sometimes this is to illuminate older texts with our latest philosophy and science; just as often this is to use the past to shine a light on the present. In either case, I prefer to bore into texts rather than to present a survey. After the first chapter, the rest are case studies, looking at texts that place matters of actions interestingly in the foreground or that have been important for the constitution of the field. The first chapter presents an overview of the philosophy of action from Hobbes to Hume and features three flash points in a century- long debate over free will. I begin with a quarrel among Civil War exiles, turn to a pamphlet war between Anthony Collins and Samuel
  • 30. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 13 Clarke fifty years later, and end with David Hume’s reflections on commercial society. The points of contention among the first two sets of writers concern what the world is made of and whether mental states have a causal function in a person’s behavior. Thomas Hobbes and Anthony Collins argue that everything is composed from a single, physical substance and therefore that a chain of cause and effect connects every one event or object to another. On this view, desires and fears have properties like atoms and apples, includ- ing the ability to cause agents to act. John Bramhall and Samuel Clarke respond that human agents will their own actions but are themselves not willed. On this view, actions happen outside the laws of causation that apply to physical objects, and human souls bear a spiritual substance different from other kinds of stuff. For his part, Hume pays attention to physical matter only to draw an analogy to actions in the social world. We never know precisely what happens when a physical cause yields a physical effect. Likewise, we never know precisely what happens when a mental cause does the same thing. In either case, we use our habits of inference and correlation to presume a relation between the one and the other. We observe something happen in nature and infer its material cause; likewise, we observe an agent doing something and infer its mental cause. The stance with respect to either is from the outside, as the private cause of any given effect recedes from view. The long debate over free will concerned not only what happens when a person acts but also from what stuff persons are made and from what point of view it is best to describe actions. Over the course of the debate, the meaning of several key terms changed. Hobbes and Hume, for example, share what I call an external outlook on actions. Yet what counts as the external changes from law, reward, and punishment in the mid-seventeenth century to commerce and interpersonal exchange a hundred years later. For Hobbes, one’s recognition of legal and political forms provided reasons for acting, while for Hume the elaborate networks of a commercial society were necessary to complete actions and make them intelligible to
  • 31. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 14 agents. This difference in perspective might be described, I argue, as one between a first- and third-person view. In the first case, an agent adjusts her desires and intentions to fit into an order of rewards and punishments; in the second, an agent looks at the actions of other people to infer how reasons serve as causes. Likewise, Bramhall and Clarke both defend human autonomy from external determina- tion, yet the former does so in the name of the soul and the latter does so in the name of common sense. Bramhall engages Hobbes in a quarrel at the not yet established borders of philosophy and theology; Clarke engages his readers’ sense that they are more than lumps of matter. The second chapter takes a close look at this relation between persons and physics. The topic is the role of consciousness and mental causation in a universe reducible to particulate matter and structured by physical laws. I say close look because, unlike the first chapter, I slice thinly through a series of late-seventeenth-century texts, looking in particular at Lucretian ideas of matter and agency and a few responses they provoke. I begin with Thomas Creech’s 1682 translation of Lucretius’ De rerum natura, the first complete translation of the poem published in English, and examine how the poem presents the emergence of whole objects from individual parts, thought from thoughtless atoms, and free movement from a universe of causes. I then trace these concerns to two writers subject to extensive treatment in later chapters. I compare Roches- ter’s translation of a few lines of the poem to Creech’s and examine their separate views of determinacy. I finish with a look at Locke’s long discussion—one equally influential and pained—of conscious- ness and personal identity in the Essay. The question broached by this chapter has two parts: how can insentient matter be the locus of thought and experience, and how can experience play a causal role in the material world? I’m interested in Lucretius because his poem tracked consciousness and mental causation to the movement of particles. The poem proposes that composite entities—people, trees, cows, what have you—take shape from the collision and
  • 32. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 15 adhesion of invisible and indivisible atoms. One trouble appears when the poem considers how atoms without thought can give rise to objects that have thought. The solution works through a process of emergence, wherein certain kinds of atoms interlock with others in such a way that consciousness comes out of them. A second area of concern appears when the poem considers what role conscious- ness has in the physical universe. The answer here is most curious. The poem makes a case for free will by distributing agency to the manifold of particulate matter. Individual atoms are thoughtless, yet they are at the same time possessed of will manifested in their random and unpredictable movement. So where the first response looks at sentience as an emergent property, the second looks at will as present in all things, a perspective we would now call panpsy- chist.23 Such attention to the small units of matter was of evident interest to Rochester, who translated two bits of Lucretius on his own along with a piece of Seneca about the “lumber” from which all things are made. Both Lucretius and Rochester write past the larger entities in which consciousness and will are incarnated. They are interested in particles, not persons. Locke’s treatment of consciousness and personal identity in the Essay presents a very different view. In what is arguably the first consistent use of the word “consciousness” in its modern sense as “the perception of what passes in a Man’s own mind,” Locke argues that consciousness provides a consistent sense of self.24 Particles come and go but selves persist over time. Accordingly, conscious selves anchor persons who are responsible for their actions and subject to eventual reward and punishment. Having made the topic of consciousness distinct from the topic of matter, however, Locke returns to their relation in the closing books of the Essay. There he engages what I describe as an early consider- ation of today’s “hard problem.” How is it, he asks, that conscious experience could arise from matter without experience? His answer follows the conundrum to its several ends. Perhaps emergent proper- ties are a brute fact of the world, or perhaps all matter bears some
  • 33. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 16 sort of experience, or perhaps matter is interwoven with spirit after all. The third chapter picks up on the discussion of Rochester begun in the second and spends considerably more time looking at how his poetry engages questions of consciousness and causation, actions and personhood. I feature Rochester because his poetry engages the physical view he encountered in Lucretius and yet extends the discussion to contexts for acting in the social and political world of the Restoration. A Satyr against Reason and Mankind, for example, asks whether mental states are able to cause anything or whether they ride along with physical causes. It toys with the idea that consciousness is only something left behind once physical causes have done all their work, or that mental causes might exist but only without agents to whom they belong. In a similar vein, Love and Life presents composite objects that have spatial parts—a hand of a person, a branch of a tree—but no equivalent temporal parts.25 An object (on this view) neither passes through time nor stretches over time, but exists only in a kind of impossible present. These musings about causation and existence over time combine in the more sexually explicit poetry—like The Imperfect Enjoyment and A Ramble in St. James’s Park—where mental states at turns get in the way of the physical system or provide a language for the system’s failure. My purpose in these readings is to show how Rochester attempts physical explanations in terms of the movement of matter. I also examine how he similarly attempts external explanations in terms of the importance of context and environment. The physical and external tend to combine or run in support of each other. Even so, Rochester doesn’t so much make neat statements on these topics as range over their many problems and difficulties, often to odd and surprising effect. For example, despite his reputation for having established desire as a basis for action, he mostly locates desire in every place beside the heads, bodies, or persons found in his poems. In keeping with this external view of an ostensibly inner phenom- enon, I draw the chapter to a close by exploring the strange fate
  • 34. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 17 of a couplet concerning mental causation from Artemiza to Chloe that was cited in a variety of works in post-1688 London. My question here is, How does a new context change the meaning of lines committed to the importance of context? The answer takes us from the manuscript coteries of the Restoration to the print public of the 1710s and ’20s, and from poetry to the essay and novel. The Rochester chapter provides one route into the eighteenth century. The fourth chapter on Locke’s theory of action provides another. Locke’s theory of consciousness had stated that there is something that it is like to have one or another thought, that the background hum of the subjective provides the underpinning of a person’s identity over time. What, if anything, do first-person thoughts or feelings have to do with acting? In Locke’s first pass at this question, the answer turns out to be “not much.” The first edition of the Essay says that we may come to full understanding of an action by observing it from the outside. One has reasons to do something and those reasons lead to actions. What it feels like to have some sort of reason has no causal role to play. The entire history of an action may therefore be plotted from an external perspective as a doing of some thing in order to accomplish some good. Locke’s frustration with this argument emerges at the outset in a series of letters exchanged with William Molyneux between the first and second edition. Molyneux asks why agents are sometimes led to error or to act against reason. He also poses to Locke his famous thought experiment about a blind man suddenly provided with sight. The point of the thought experiment—the Molyneux Problem, as it will be subsequently known—is to emphasize the importance of first-person experience in understanding the external world. The blind man comes to new knowledge about the cubes and spheres he had previously touched when he sees them for the first time. The analogous suggestion for a theory of actions is that one learns something new about them in light of the feelings with which they were accompanied. The second edition of the Essay takes this new argument to heart and presents a thoroughly revised model of
  • 35. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 18 actions. In the first edition, the cause of any action was always one’s reason for doing whatever one did. In the second, it is always one’s wanting to achieve some desired end. Alongside this new emphasis on desire as a causal faculty, Locke places a new term—“uneasi- ness”—which describes what it feels like to desire something. Seen from the outside and the third person, desire is the cause of actions. Seen from the inside and the first person, desire is experienced as uneasiness. Without having a sense of this uneasiness, one can’t tell exactly what any given agent will do or has done. Consciousness provides additional information to what one gathers from observ- ing the behavior of agents. This view is in some ways compatible with what we sometimes think we know about early-eighteenth-century literary history. So the chapter ends with a brief treatment of Catharine Trotter, a playwright and novelist who also wrote a treatise in defense of Locke’s philosophy. I don’t turn to Trotter just to track the contro- versies surrounding the publication of the Essay. (Trotter’s was one text among many written against or in defense of Locke at the time.) Rather, I’m interested in Trotter because she provides a concrete example of the explicit and sign-posted theory of actions— the kind of thing that would appear in a treatise—making its way into the implicit staging ground of narrative fiction. Trotter had one foot in each. One of the selling points of the kind of epistolary fiction Trotter wrote was that it provided a first-person perspec- tive on causes of action. Locke had said that desire causes actions and is experienced as uneasiness. Trotter’s novel and others like it attempted to color in what that might mean and how it might work. Assertion of this kind has often led to a related claim that novels express the priority of the psychological and of a particular person’s private experience, an argument associated with Ian Watt’s famous book on the novel, though perhaps one as old as serious consider- ation of the genre. I don’t intend to overturn this argument so much as give it a little bit of trouble. The final two chapters of the book are thus focused on eighteenth-century fiction and attempt to show
  • 36. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 19 how a causal account of actions might or might not make recourse to the interior states of agents. I’ve chosen two authors whose works seem to feature problems of agency in interesting and opposed ways, and who are, respec- tively, a subject of intense, recent interest and a perennial favorite. I look at Eliza Haywood because she sustains the sort of commitment to experience and feelings that Locke and Trotter promote without also committing herself to accompanying notions of the interior point of view or the separateness of personhood from environment. Few writers of the period are more extravagant than Haywood in their language of passionate feeling. So much is intuitively obvious. My argument will be that Haywood stops short of assigning these feelings to discrete persons or objects. The common-sense bonding of experience to a subject of experience begins to loosen across a range of incidents but is especially fraught and intriguing, I argue, with the concept and experience of consent. Consent is a term understood by Locke and others to join private experience to formal contracts like marriage or impersonal structures like the state. In these highly significant venues, it validates external authorities with the imprimatur of the subjective. I wasn’t dragged to the altar; I freely consented to marry this toad. The reign of this king or parliament isn’t arbitrary; we consent to be governed. And so on. The trouble is how to get from the possession to the expression of consent. How do we know if someone actually consents? How do I know that I have consented? The question poses the real quandary of accessing mental states, phenomena that are difficult, some said impossible, to view directly. The “How can I know if someone has consented?” question is, in this respect, a sharpened version of the “How can I see what another person is thinking or feeling?” question. Locke’s answer is that you can’t and so you don’t. He outlines instead two forms of externalization: the actual “expression” of consent in forms of contractual stipulation, like oaths, charters, and vows, and the tacit enacting of consent in daily life. I’m especially interested in “tacit consent” because it attaches such a consequential entailment
  • 37. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 20 to the most quotidian of activities. One person buys an item in a store; another takes a turn in a carriage; both have consented to be governed. Out of the minutest incidents of mental causation rise the grandest edifices of liberal democracy. Between mental causes and civil societies are a series of finely grained steps: the kind of dailyness of thought and action dwelt upon in works of fiction. Such will be my gambit, at least, in considering Haywood’s Love in Excess (1719) and Fantomina (1725). These will be unsurprising picks for anyone who has been paying attention to the directions of eighteenth-century literary studies for the past decade, and that is partly my point. Our attention has been drawn to these works because, among other things, they are interested in teasing through the kind of problems addressed by the dual nature of consent, as something mental and something external. Locke’s problem concerns the enactment of internally held mental states and concepts. Haywood’s response is to show that there is no we or I doing the consenting, or, in a slightly different vein, to say that consent is in the doing, not in the expressing. One should, I think, be careful about generalizing across kinds of writing. After all, Haywood does not have the same kind of expository obligations as Locke. Instead, she uses the advantages of formal experimentation, especially in third-person evocations of tremulous feeling, to show how mental states are as much in the world as in the head, as much subject to the needs of plot as something one brings to other people or larger institutions. Readers might expect an account of Richardson to pursue an opposite line of argument. Arguably no writer of the period is more conventionally associated with first-person experience and the authority of the self in advance of external circumstance. That is not the argument I make, but neither do I simply pursue the contrary line and suggest that our most storied novel of first-person experi- ence really places mental states outside the mind or the person. I end with Clarissa, rather, because its multiperspective version of epistolary form is so suited to explore the several models of action
  • 38. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 21 available in the eighteenth-century thought world. With this ending in mind, I return to the basic ontological question around actions with which I began, now pitched toward a work of fiction written a century after the discussion of agency took off with Hobbes. The ontological question is, How do we pick actions from the larger class of events? The answer (again) is that actions involve mental states while other events do not. Discussion of the nature of actions thus turned on the status of this involvement. Did mental states cause actions, and if so were they also caused? From what point of view—internal or external, first or third person—should actions be described? Clarissa zeros in on these questions by presenting them from more than one vantage, as the few yet weighty events in the novel come under painstaking description from several angles. The novel makes clear, for example, that another way to ask about actions is to count them. We ask about events in general when we ask if anything has happened; we ask about actions in particular when we ask whether anyone has done anything. Clarissa is particu- larly interesting in this regard because so much of the tension comes down to enumeration. Consider the conflict at Harlowe Place. Clarissa’s family treats her refusal of Solmes as an act against them; Clarissa doesn’t consider her refusal an action at all. The quarrel isn’t just over why she has done one or another thing; it is firstly whether she has actually done anything. So Clarissa finds herself explaining to her family that she hasn’t taken any action against them, while they view her as continually acting in ways contrary to their interests. To help make sense of this conflict I make recourse to an updated version of the eighteenth-century philosophy of action, Elizabeth Anscombe’s famous account of intentional actions as those “under a description.”26 One point of Anscombe’s little volume, Intention (1957), was to show how actions come into view when the question “Why?” is asked of them. Events present themselves as a mass of unincorporated detail. Put them under a description and the focus sharpens some. A young woman’s legs move up and down. A pair
  • 39. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 22 of shoes covers itself with mud. A young woman gets into a carriage with a young man. A young woman runs away with a libertine. A libertine kidnaps a young woman. These are separate accounts of the same thing. The shoes get dirty as her legs move as she gets into the carriage as she runs away or is kidnapped. Depending on which description you choose, the event seems very different; indeed, only in the latter two accounts is the event at all recognizable in the terms suggested by the novel. So then the quarrel over enumerating actions revolves around whether and how one apportions intentions in the description one provides. The last two accounts subsume the earlier ones because they provide the intention with which the action is done, and (crucially) the intention belongs to a different agent in each. Clarissa’s way of protecting herself is often to deny a causal role in the actions she appears to take. I did not mean to fly away with a libertine or to harm my family or to lose my honor. I certainly did not cause any of these things to happen. She may have intentions but they are rarely intentions with which any actions are done; they are more likely to be intendings to do some future thing. This to say that Clarissa holds on to an internal view of actions and tends to avoid causal accounts of her own behavior. The “direction of fit,” as readers of Anscombe would put it, is world to mind.27 Clarissa attempts to “fit” the world to her intendings. The conflict with Lovelace that preoccupies the middle sections of the novel appears when the “direction of fit” moves in the other way, as Lovelace attempts to shape intendings to a world that precedes them. Richardson writes of Lovelace, in this respect, as one committed to an externalist account of mental states. Nowhere is this more heated than in the consideration of consent. Lovelace arranges appear- ances and circumstances so that it seems that Clarissa has already consented to lose her virtue and voluntarily live with him out of wedlock. He is frustrated and aghast when her consent does not fit the situation at hand. Both Lovelace and Clarissa are committed to the notion that mental states individuate actions. On his view,
  • 40. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 23 mental states emerge out of necessity from the causal order in which they are placed, so the appearance of Clarissa’s consent should be the same as the existence of her consent. On her view, one’s experi- ence of one’s mental states is prior to their place in any outside order of things. Clarissa is a nice place to end, in this respect, because the ongoing discussion of actions both shapes and is responded to by some of the features we have come to recognize as integral to the midcentury novel, especially in the Richardsonian mode: from claims to first-person authority, to the contesting friction of overlap- ping perspectives. In this case, the competition between the several accounts of action takes off against the view that would see them as compatible with determination. For his part, Lovelace wants nothing to do with the notion that anyone’s behavior is both free and determined. Intentions are supposed to conform to the world in the manner of a belief. For her part, Clarissa insists on her power to act even as it becomes impossible to do so. Intentions outlast the environment they face. The novel is thus among other things a vast tapestry woven around the idea of compatibilism first set forth a hundred years earlier. I close the book with a consideration of Clarissa’s death because it is in the novel’s reflecting on whether the death is a suicide that the topic of actions joins to the problems around consciousness and mental causation I feature at the beginning. Clarissa wants to die yet will not kill herself or act in any way that furthers her demise. The avoiding of suicide thus picks out mental properties from the flux of physical causes. Death is one among many physical events. The prohibition against suicide—like that against murder—alights on the mental and, in so doing, fastens on its causal role. The clarity in which this may be stated reveals something interesting, I argue, about the final sections of the novel: mental causation is easier to envisage when it is related to the destruction of the person, precisely the entity imagined to be the locus of such causes. This is not an isolated phenomenon. The long consideration of Clarissa’s possible suicide occurs at a historical moment when the materialist question-
  • 41. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 24 ing of personal identity had reached the topic of ending one’s life. First codified in Augustine’s ruminations on Lucretia, the prohibition against suicide takes as its premise that a person is distinct from her physical body.28 On this view, Clarissa is not just a mass of atoms; she is an entity made in imitation of God. Yet on the view of others (including Hume), the prohibition against suicide marks out mental causes only to make them superfluous, rendering the providential design of the causal order something that ought not to be disturbed by states of mind. For some, even, the appropriate response was to say that persons were no different from any other composite entity and mental causes the same as their physical counterparts. On this view, the destruction of the person is merely the return of matter to the cosmos from which all things are made. This is not the view provided by the novel, of course, which endeavors to show how Clarissa is not only more than her parts but also more than a person in the conventional meaning subscribed to by other writers in her midst. The answer the novel provides to the twin problems of consciousness and mental causation thus turns out to be less of a normal or conventional one than one that is, in its own way, just as peculiar as those seen earlier in Rochester and elsewhere. It is possible to imagine a world in which there are only events and no actions.29 It is not likely that we, or anything like us, would be in this world. But nevertheless such a world is possible. Subtract every agent and this counterfactual world looms into view: earthquakes happen, comets shoot by, and yet no one does anything. There probably wouldn’t be any mental properties in this world, and if there were, they would be causally inert with respect to the pageant of events in their midst. Everything would be caused by physical properties alone. This world has a kind of simplicity and elegance. It is, however, not the world we live in. Were it so, I would not be writing this sentence nor would you be turning these pages. The actual world is one in which some events have mental causes. When we pick these events out, we, as the expression goes, carve nature
  • 42. Introduction: Nothing from Nothing 25 at its joints.30 We pare some events into actions, a class defined by their causal history. My argument is that the century roughly between Hobbes and Hume or Rochester and Richardson did just that, and in so doing endeavored to discover the component parts of actions in a way analogous to the discovery of anything else in nature. Once upon a time this sort of argument might have been made with particular reference to the interior life of characters or voice of poems, a life or voice that corresponds to something like the motives and mental causes of human agents. Perhaps for this reason, when Anscombe sought to discount motives in her study of intentions, she said in passing, “I am very glad not to be writing either ethics or literary criticism, to which this question belongs.”31 For Anscombe, motives along with mental causes were inherently obscure, whereas intentions could be read off the surface of one’s behavior. An intentional action is not a series of doings plus an inner, private motive. It is rather the kind of action for which one may supply a description of why it was done. Anscombe’s attempt to analyze an ostensibly mental-state term while holding at bay catego- ries of the mind is crisp and seductive. Even so, it is perhaps a virtue of writing literary criticism that one sees how even the more mind- centered works of the period do not necessarily imply a language of privacy or inwardness, selfhood or the individual. Some of the works I feature are interested in these categories, but just as many are not. What I will argue in the following chapters is this: the topic of actions involved mental terms (including intentions) as a particu- lar kind of cause. A close look at all kinds of texts shows that these causes move in several directions, sometimes from within but just as often from without. It is (again) possible to imagine a world that has only events, with no actions. It is very difficult to imagine a world that has no causes. Admitting causation into the account of actions left a shudder. The works I look at are a few instances where that shudder is most intriguingly recorded.
  • 44. 1 Actions, Agents, Causes The period covered by this study witnesses an important debate about actions. For writers like Hobbes and Hume, human behavior really ought to be described in causal terms. When trying to make sense of what a person does, it is always best to examine the reasons that cause and explain her actions. These reasons typically turn out to be the desires and beliefs an agent has about the effects of her actions, attitudes that are in turn caused by events external to the agent herself.1 The view that actions are caused by attitudes like desire and belief comes under scrutiny, however, from those who think that causal arguments put at risk one’s autonomy and freedom, especially when causes are understood to track back to the outside world. While Hobbes and Hume found causal necessity to be compatible with freedom, their opponents saw freedom as incompatible with any sort of external dependence. My goal in this chapter is to show how this debate encloses a range of philosophi- cal, social, and literary concerns. Foremost among them is whether persons are special kinds of agents, endowed with immaterial souls, or whether mental states like desire and belief are made of the same stuff as the rest of the world and thus susceptible to a kind of limitless causation. Within this metaphysical quarrel over person- hood, talk about reasons for action—one’s motives, say—often entailed further talk about the societies in which actions occur. As a result, debates about agency had considerable bearing on questions of authority in an age that begins with civil wars and ends with a commercial empire. To look at the motives that lie behind actions was for many to examine how states of mind bring about forms of
  • 45. Actions, Agents, Causes 28 politics or society. Yet states of mind like motive or intention were often impossible to understand apart from the context in which they occurred. And so the moral of this chapter for the larger project of the book is this: if the philosophy of action consistently found itself tugged between an account of agency that secluded the will within the mind and an account that derived it from external causes, so too did the literary forms designed to evoke the reaches of human consciousness and action. In either case, the line between persons and their component parts, persons and society, the mind and the body, one mind and another, all come under meaningful pressure.2 Free Will or Necessity, Part 1 Our story begins with Royalist exiles living in Paris during the early years of the Civil War. In 1645 William Cavendish, the Marquess of Newcastle, commissioned Thomas Hobbes and the Anglican theolo- gian John Bramhall to write on the free will problem, a venerable concern of philosophers made relevant again by religious and politi- cal upheaval. Bramhall composed a short paper that spring and Hobbes responded quickly; Bramhall rebutted, and the exchange remained for a time within a small group of expatriates. Upon their return to England, however, the debate took a more public face. In 1654 Hobbes’s paper was printed and published, without his permission, under the title Of Libertie and Necessitie. Bramhall followed the next year by publishing his rejoinder, A Defence of True Liberty, from Antecedent and Extrinsecall Necessity. Hobbes replied with a new paper, The Questions concerning Liberty, Necessity, and Chance, in 1656. Two years later, Bramhall returned with Castigations of Mr. Hobbes his Last Animadversions in the Case concerning Liberty, and Universal Necessity. By this time, the debate had moved from a manuscript coterie to a print public and in the process taken on the formal dimensions of a major contro- versy, with each writer stating his theses in point-by-point response to the other and anticipating and refuting arguments in advance.3
  • 46. Actions, Agents, Causes 29 Much of the controversy centered on how one might go about defining what actions are, where they start and where they stop. When Hobbes describes an action, he refers to an event with a causal history. Agent P has done action R for reason Q. It is not enough to say that P had Q while doing R; rather, in order to be part of the description, Q must explain the occurrence of R. Consider the following set of events: “[W]hen a Travailer meets with a shower, the journey had a cause, and the rain had a cause sufficient to produce it, but because the journey caused not the rain, nor the rain the journey, we say, they were contingent one to another” and not related as cause and effect.4 The conclusion Hobbes wishes to derive from the example is simple. The rain happened at the same time as the traveler’s journey but did not cause him to go, an action that was presumably caused by the desire to get from one place to another. The weather and a person’s decisions each have a causal structure that prominently features reasons. This structure bears on the free will problem because it tethers the will to something on its outside. The agent who decides to go on a journey does so for a reason, and, that being the case, her will has locked onto whatever disposition or attitude explains her action. “In this following of ones hopes and fears,” Hobbes writes, “consisteth the nature of Election,” by which he means that choosing to act refers to a cause (a hope or fear) and does not occur on its own.5 So when a philosopher leaves London for Paris in the midst of civil war, he does so presumably because he wants to be in Paris and believes that traveling to Dover and getting on a boat is a good way of getting there. He may further believe, given his Royalist sympathies, that being in Paris is a good idea in the hour of Republican victory. Adding further reasons, however, only sews more stitches to the causal net. It’s enough to say at this point that he left because he wanted to be in Paris, for by describing events this way we commit to the idea that “all actions have their causes” (Questions, 70). To describe an action that an agent performs, one needs to provide the reason for which it was done. One can do so, Hobbes
  • 47. Actions, Agents, Causes 30 argues, by looking at the sundry passions of the mind, in particular those organized around “appetite and fear . . . the first unperceived beginnings of our actions.”6 This use of a mental vocabulary is important (for the moment) to satisfy the requirement that the will, like everything else, has a cause. We have on Hobbes’s account provided a description of his decision to take a boat to Paris if we say he feared the Parliamentary army and wanted to be safe among friends. Our description of his actions, however, makes an argument against his will having been free to take them. That is because providing a causal account of actions also supplies the grounds of their necessity, the locking of choice onto the attitude by which it is explained. When, for example, Hobbes argues that the Lord having said to David, “I offer thee three things; choose thee one of them, that I may do it unto thee” (2 Samuel, 24:12), is not evidence for free will, he claims that one cannot show that “such election was not necessitated by the hopes, and fears, and considerations of good and bad to follow” (Libertie, 7). God affords to David the opportunity to choose among options, but the act of choosing one thing over another requires there to be a reason for doing so, and this requirement locks the will onto the particular hope or fear that rationalizes the choice. Seen this way, the idea of free will is a category mistake, since it ascribes to an appetite a condition that can belong only to an agent, and since it attempts thereby to shed the causes that explain why one takes the actions one does. Bramhall holds in contrast that “all the freedom of the agent is from the freedom of the will,” a position he articulates in opposi- tion to causal accounts of acting.7 We have sufficiently described an action, on his view, if we say merely that it was undertaken by the will. No lattice of causes trails behind this singular faculty. And so while agents may be said to have reasons for acting the way they do, those reasons never quite exert the force of a cause into an effect. A reason might “representeth to the will, whether this or that be convenient” but the will always retains the right to choose what to do in response to this information (Defence, 10).
  • 48. Actions, Agents, Causes 31 When “the will is mooved by the understanding,” for example, it is “not as by an efficient, having a causall influence into the effect, but only by proposing and representing the object” (Defence, 31). In the gap between the reason that proposes objects and the will that acts upon them lies the vaunted freedom from necessity, for “whatsoever obligation the understanding does put upon the will, is by the consent of the will, and derived from the power of the will, which was not necessitated to moove the understanding to consult” (Defence, 30). Where Hobbes tracks motives into actions, therefore, Bramhall reverses course and sets the will apart from any motive one might have, as if the will were a kind of person within the mind. The result is an elaborate allegory of agency, in which “the will is the Lady and Mistris of human actions, the understanding is her trusty counseller, which gives no advice, but when it is required by the will” (Defence, 30–1). Lest this seem too close to a cause moving into an effect, Bramhall further observes that “if the first consultation or deliberation be not sufficient, the will may moove a review, and require the understanding to inform it self better” (Defence, 31).8 The effort is at once to sheathe the will from causes and provide for it a kind of psychology of choosing. To be a person, on this view, is to be possessed of a will that can refuse to follow motives or desires. Thus the proper tense in which to describe acts of a free will is the past conditional. Despite the preponderance of causes, free agents “might have suspended or denied [the] concur- rence” of past actions or might “have elected otherwise” (Defence, 11, 209).9 One important corollary of Bramhall’s account of actions is that their proper description really ought not to extend beyond the agent. Insofar as the will is always free to do otherwise, the history of an action should make reference to events within the mind only. In pointed contrast, Hobbes argues that the description of actions should be as extensive as possible. This kind of description, as we have seen, begins by making reference to reasons. Hobbes got on a boat because he wanted to get to Paris. Agent P did action R for
  • 49. Actions, Agents, Causes 32 reason Q. The more closely one looks at Q, however, the more one sees that it is caused by Q1, Q2, and so on. Hobbes wanted to get to Paris because he feared for his safety in London. He feared for his safety in London because he believed his writings had angered the Parliamentary authorities. Once opened up to inspection, the causal horizon is nearly limitless. “That which I say necessitateth and determineth every action,” Hobbes writes, “is the sum of all those things, which being now existent, conduce and concurre to the production of that action hereafter, whereof if any one thing now were wanting, the effect could not be produced” (Questions, 80).10 The sum of all things can stretch quite far. At the very least, it can extend beyond the minds of agents to the circumstances and contexts in which agents find themselves. So while it is true that actions depend upon mental states, it is also true that mental states arise from objects, events, and occurrences, from causes external to the head. When Hobbes writes that “nothing taketh beginning from itself” he means to include not only the will but also what we might think of as the efficient cause of the will, the attitude to which the will is locked. Both are brought about by causes not of the agent’s “disposing” (Questions, 289). While propositional attitudes like wanting to get to Paris or believing that a boat might do the trick may seem like they begin within us, as mental terms ostensibly should, their proper description, Hobbes argues, ought to reach from the mind to the world. This is because stopping with the mind’s internal repertoire of attitudes would fall short of the story in which one comes to have attitudes locked to actions. The route accordingly moves from the outside in: “[E]xternal objects cause conceptions, and conceptions appetite and fear”—and appetite and fear the various acts of the will.11 This particular dimension to Hobbes’s quarrel with free will is worth a moment’s pause. The locking of the will onto attitudes like wanting or fearing, knowing or believing, had seemed to commit Hobbes to a kind of inward account of actions, one that specified their causal history in terms of a mental vocabulary of desires or
  • 50. Actions, Agents, Causes 33 intentions. But on further inspection it turns out that Hobbes is equally committed to describing the history of actions with respect to their peripheral beginnings, in contexts beyond the person.12 The long-term result, I will argue over the course of this book, is a balancing of events internal to agents with the external forms by which these events are shaped. Causation casts too wide a net to capture only the propositional attitudes leading up to actions. So it will be important for us to keep an eye on the varieties of external- ism that begin for our purposes with Hobbes and extend into the middle of the eighteenth century with Hume—to look, that is, at accounts of action that track attitudes past agents having them to the worlds from which attitudes spring, to societies and polities, to physical units of matter, or simply to other people.13 Hobbes’s version, as we have seen, places emphasis on the near limitless reach of causation, the “sum of all things” that issue into a particu- lar action. “There is hardly one Action, to the causing of which concurres not whatsoever is in rerum natura,” Hobbes writes, and then adds as if to explain, that “there cannot be a Motion in one part of the World, but the same must also be communicated to all the rest of the World” (Questions, 239). Hobbes thus elaborates a concept of cause that binds atoms to thoughts to persons to kings to God. On this view, actions don’t so much begin with agents as fall backward along a continuous web. The inclusion of any one action within a web of antecedent causes makes an important statement about the nature of persons, as Hobbes’s critics were wont to show. If causation doesn’t begin with the will, but rather with attitudes and before that with reasons for those attitudes, then the special place of the person in the overall scheme of the cosmos has been taken away. On the most basic sense of things, Hobbes does not consider persons to be differ- ent in substance from other entities in the world. His description of the universe—in which “every Object is either a part of the whole World, or an Aggregate of parts”—admits of one substance, reducible in all instances to the atoms that make up minds and
  • 51. Actions, Agents, Causes 34 bodies alike.14 I will explore in the next chapter some of the difficul- ties that come with this sort of physical model of consciousness and mental causation. I would like now to stick to the place of agents in a world where action occurs as a motion across a single chain. Consider Bramhall’s writing a response to Hobbes. Bramhall ascribes to this act a “moral” foundation that begins within him. Hobbes retorts, “I doubt not but he had therefore the Will to write this Reply, because I had answered his Treatise concerning true Liberty. My answer therefore was (at least in part) the cause of his writing, yet that is the cause of the nimble local motion of his fingers. Is not the cause of local motion Physical? His will therefore was Physically and Extrinsecally and Antecedently, and not Morally caused by my writing” (Questions, 142–3). The turn to reasons outside the agent flanks an emphasis on physical description. One motion across the surface of things takes us from Hobbes’s writing to the movement of Bramhall’s fingers to the appearance of another essay, all without much pause for a person having a will that expresses itself in writing. When Hobbes adds to this account that “what it is to determine a thing Morally, no man living understands,” he gets rid of the chance that there might be something in agents—a moral center—that stops the motion of cause and leaves space for an authority over one’s own will (Questions, 142). Bramhall’s feeling that his essay has no cause other than his will to write it, and that having this will is quite close to what it means to be human, misrecognizes on Hobbes’s view the nature of causal relations in a physical world. There is no space outside of matter that belongs to the soul or the will or the passions or anything else one might want to use as a platform for autonomy.15 Hobbes asks Bramhall to give up the intuitive sense that he is the cause of his own actions and that any particular action he performed could always have gone otherwise. Bramhall’s error, in other words, is to hew too closely to common sense—“that which he sayes, any thing else whatsoever, would think, if it knew it were moved, and did not know what moved it”—rather than to look into the sources
  • 52. Actions, Agents, Causes 35 of his actions (Questions, 41). The feeling one has of free will is intuitive only if one is ignorant of causes, a point that leads Hobbes on a certain rhetorical flourish: “A wooden Top that is lasht by the Boyes, and runs about sometimes to one Wall, sometimes to another, sometimes spinning, sometimes hitting men on the shins, if it were sensible of its own motion, would think it proceeded from its own Will, unless it felt what lasht it” (Questions, 41). The notion of human action as a special kind of event is on this metaphorical description vividly reduced, as if to suggest that we are little more than conscious tops, spun by causes beyond our immediate percep- tion. The metaphor makes two related points, first that autonomy is a kind of delusion and second that events internal to the mind follow the same laws of causation as events external to the mind. Hobbes’s inclusion of mental causation under the same laws as physical causation serves an important purpose. If the will is locked to attitudes and attitudes are locked to objects, thoughts, or events, then human action is subject to the same necessity as everything else in the world. At the same time, however, this necessity does not deprive agents of freedom or of responsibility. Here lies one of Hobbes’s more notable contributions to models of agency in the early modern and modern periods. Hobbes argues that freedom requires only that a person is able to act according to her wants, not that the will is without a determining set of causes. “A free agent,” on this view, is he “that can do if he will, and forbear if he will” and liberty the “absence of external impediments” to action (Questions, 304, 46).16 Freedom turns out to be a particular kind of causal relation, one in which reasons are able to become actions. The condition of freedom is therefore satisfied if the reasons one has proceed uninhibited into the actions one takes. On this account, no amount of determinacy conflicts with freedom, since the having of attitudes is what it means to be an agent and since the translat- ing of attitudes without hindrance into actions is what it means to have liberty. To put the problem in terms of our earlier example, it makes no sense to ask whether Hobbes’s will was free to choose
  • 53. Actions, Agents, Causes 36 going to France but it does to ask whether Hobbes was free to leave or whether the authorities intercepted his boat. “A Free Agent” is one “whose motion, or action is not hindered nor stopt. And a Free Action, that which is produced by a Free Agent” (Questions, 143). The forming of a will to do something, then, is part of the causal history of an action but alone is neither free nor bound; these conditions belong only to the agent and action themselves. What will later be termed compatibilism is a simple yet important argument: to describe something in terms of its causal history does nothing to put liberty at risk.17 Rather, it is to take a close look at that thing and examine its component parts. So to say that a person acts for a reason is both to explain why actions occur and to say that a person could not have done otherwise, since doing otherwise would mean only that she had another will, locked to a separate series of events. Freedom therefore does not require that I am set loose from a net of causes; it simply demands that “I can do if I will,” a condition met by there being no obstacles to my doing. Hobbes’s compatibilism will (again) have a significant influence on seventeenth- and eighteenth-century philosophy, from Locke and Hume, who both embraced it after their own fashions, to Kant, who found it to be a “wretched subterfuge.”18 If one appeal of the argument was its sense that actions become intelligible only once we realize, often against our intuitions, that their sources are extensive, another is the claim that having reasons for acting takes nothing away from the accountability one incurs along the way. The contex- tual sources of action, on Hobbes’s account, bind agents to external structures, a claim he evidently found convenient in a time of politi- cal uncertainty. “The necessity of an action doth not make the Laws that prohibit it unjust,” Hobbes writes in response to Bramhall’s worry that a commitment to necessity would mean that “praise, dispraise, reward and punishment are in vain” (Libertie, 27). Bramhall believes the doctrine of free will is required for systems of politics and morality to be legitimate, since without it agents would neither be nor feel accountable for their actions; thus even
  • 54. Actions, Agents, Causes 37 the “perswasion that there is no true liberty is able to overthrow all Societies and Commonwealths in the world” (Defence, 91). For his part, Hobbes finds in necessity the very basis of obedience and order. Agents come to have intentions, desires, and beliefs because they witness consequences in the world about them; in this way, “praise and dispraise, and likewise Reward and Punishment, do by example make and conform the will to good and evil” (Libertie, 34). This exchange repeats their disagreement over the role of causal language in the description of actions, this time with reference to political obligation. Hobbes argues that believing that actions have consequences is reason, in most cases, to conform one’s behavior to Scripture and polity, and when it is not, to fear the extraper- sonal laws of God and the state. The external antecedents to action turn out to be the very laws one ought to be obeying. From this perspective, Bramhall’s claim that the will acts on its own discovers autonomy where there is none and as a result cleaves agents from their sources of compliance. I will come back in subsequent chapters to the seventeenth-century quarrel over the sources and meanings of actions. Before turning to the next installment, I want to gather some of the threads of the controversy as I have reconstructed it so far. Much centered on the significance of the concept of cause in the description of actions, on whether cause was essential to understanding connections among the diverse phenomena of the mind and world or whether it was a threat to the special nature and place of humans in the cosmos. Under the rubric of cause, Hobbes and Bramhall disagreed about, for example, whether persons are endowed with immaterial souls or whether persons are entirely physical in their composition. As a corollary to that disagreement, they quarreled over the point where actions started and stopped—within the precincts of the will or in attitudes and contexts. Without simplifying too much, then, we might draw the quarrel over cause into one between an immate- rialist, dualist, and internalist picture of agency, on the one hand, and a physicalist, monist, and externalist picture on the other. For
  • 55. Random documents with unrelated content Scribd suggests to you:
  • 56. sniffles, carrying a slate and geography in one hand, and leading a little sister by the other, who also sniffles and stares. This, too, is Greater New York, Borough of Richmond, better known as Staten Island. This borough has nearly all kinds of wild and tame rurality and suburbanity. Its farms need not be described. III Pointing out mere farms in the city becomes rather monotonous; they are too common. But there is one kind of farm in New York that is not at all common, that has never existed in any other city, so far as I know, in ancient or modern times. It is situated, oddly enough, in about the centre of the 317 square miles of New York—so well as the centre of a boot-shaped area can be located.
  • 57. There is profitable oyster-dredging in several sections of the city. Cross Thirty-fourth Street Ferry to Long Island City, which really does not smell so bad as certain of our poets would have us believe; take the car marked Steinway, and ride for fifteen or twenty minutes out through dreary city edge, past small, unpainted manufactories, squalid tenements, dirty backyards, and sad vacant lots that serve as the last resting-place for decayed trucks and overworked wagons. Soon after passing a tumble-down windmill, which looks like an historic old relic, on a hill-top, but which was built in 1867 and tumbled down only recently, the Steinway Silk Mills will be reached (they can be distinguished by the long, low wings of the building covered with windows like a hothouse). Leave the car here and strike off to the left, down the lane which will soon be an alley, and then a hundred yards or so from the highway will be seen the first of the odd, paper-covered houses of a colony of Chinese farmers who earn their living by tilling the soil of Greater New York. At short distances are the other huts crouching at the foot of big trees, with queer gourds hanging out in front to dry, and large unusual crocks lying about, and huge baskets, and mattings—all clearly from China; they are as different from what could be bought on the neighboring avenue as the farm and farmers themselves are different from most Long Island farms and farmers. Out in the fields, which are tilled in the Oriental way, utilizing every inch of ground clean up to the fence, and laid out with even divisions at regular intervals, like rice-fields, the farmers themselves may be seen, working with Chinese implements, their pigtails tucked up under their straw hats, while the western world wags on in its own way all around them. This is less than five miles from the glass-covered parade-ground of the Waldorf-Astoria. They have only three houses among them, that is, there are only three of these groups of rooms, made of old boards and boxes and covered with tar paper; but no one in the neighborhood seems to
  • 58. know just how many Chinamen live there. The same sleeping space would hold a score or more over in Pell Street. Being Chinamen, they grow only Chinese produce, a peculiar kind of bean and some sort of salad, and those large, artistic shaped melons, seen only in China or Chinatown, which they call something that sounds like moncha, and which, one of them told me, bring two cents a pound from the Chinese merchants and restaurateurs of Manhattan. For my part, I was very glad to learn of these farms, for I had always been perplexed to account for the fresh salads and green vegetables, of unmistakably Chinese origin, that can be found in season in New York's Chinatown. Under an old shed near by they have their market-wagon, in which, looking inscrutable, they drive their stuff to market through Long Island City, and by way of James Slip Ferry over to Chinatown; then back to the farm again, looking inscrutable. And on Sundays, for all we know, they leave the wagon behind and go to gamble their earnings away in Mott Street, or perhaps away over in some of the well-known places of Jersey City. Then back across the two ferries to farming on dreary Monday mornings. IV Even up in Manhattan there are still places astonishingly unlike what is expected of the crowded little island on which stands New York proper. There is Fort Washington with tall trees growing out of the Revolutionary breastworks, land, under their branches, a fine view up the Hudson to the mountains—a quiet, sequestered bit of public park which the public hasn't yet learned to treat as a park, though within sight of the crowds crossing the viaduct from the Grant Monument on Riverside. There are wild flowers up there every spring, and until quite recently so few people visited this spot for days at a time that there were sometimes woodcock and perhaps other game in the thickly wooded ravine by the railroad. Soon,
  • 59. however, the grass on the breastworks will be worn off entirely, and the aged deaf man who tends the river light on Jeffreys Hook will become sophisticated, if he is still alive. Cemetery Ridge, Near Richmond, Staten Island. It will take longer, however, for the regions to the north, beyond Washington Heights, down through Inwood and past Tubby Hook, to look like part of a city. And across the Spuyten Duyvil Creek from Manhattan Island, up through the winding roads of Riverdale to Mount St. Vincent, and so across the line to Yonkers, it is still wooded, comparatively secluded and country-like, even though so many of the fine country places thereabouts are being deserted. Over to the eastward, across Broadway, a peaceful road which does not look like a part of the same thoroughfare as the one with actors and sky-scrapers upon it, there are the still wilder stretches of Mosholu and Van Cortlandt Park, where, a year or two ago, large, well-painted signs on the trees used to say Beware of the Buffaloes.
  • 60. A Peaceful Scene in New York. In the distance is St. Andrew's Church, Borough of Richmond, Staten Island. The open country sport of golf has had a good deal to do with making this rural park more generally appreciated. Golf has done for Van Cortlandt what the bicycle had done for the Bronx and Pelham Bay Parks. There are still natural, wild enough looking bits, off from the beaten paths, in all these parks, scenes that look delightfully dark and sylvan in the yearly thousands of amateur photographs— the camera does not show the German family approaching from the rear, or the egg-shells and broken beer-bottles behind the bushes— but beware of the police if you break a twig, or pick a blossom. V Those who enjoy the study of all the forms of nature except the highest can find plenty to sigh over in the way the city thrusts itself upon the country. But to those who think that the haunts and habits
  • 61. of the Man are not less worthy of observation than those of the Beaver and the Skunk, it is all rather interesting, and some of it not so deeply deplorable. A Relic of the Early Nineteenth Century, Borough of Richmond. There are certain old country taverns, here and there, up toward Westchester, and down beyond Brooklyn and over on Staten Island— not only those which everybody knows, like the Hermitage in the Bronx and Garrisons over by the fort at Willets Point, but remote ones which have not yet been exploited in plays or books, and which still have a fine old flavor, with faded prints of Dexter and Maud S. and much earlier favorites in the bar-room. In some cases, to be sure, though still situated at a country cross-roads, with green fields all about, they are now used for Tammany head-quarters with pictures of the new candidate for sheriff in the old-fashioned windows—but most of them would have gone out of existence entirely after the death of the stage-coach, if it had not been for the approach of the city, and the side-whiskered New Yorkers of a previous generation who drove fast horses. If the ghosts of these
  • 62. men ever drive back to lament the good old days together, they must be somewhat surprised, possibly disappointed, to find these rural road-houses doing a better business than even in their day. The bicycle revived the road-house, and though the bicycle has since been abandoned by those who prefer fashion to exercise, the places that the wheel disclosed are not forgotten. They are visited now in automobiles. An Old-fashioned Stone-arched Bridge. (Richmond, Staten Island.) There are all those historic country-houses within the city limits, well known, and in some cases restored, chiefly by reason of being within the city, like the Van Cortlandt house, now a part of the park, and the Jumel mansion standing over Manhattan Field, a house which gets into most historical novels of New York. Similarly Claremont Park has adopted the impressive Zabriskie mansion; and the old Lorillard house in the Bronx might have been torn down by this time but that it has been made into a park house and restaurant. Nearly all these are tableted by the patriotic societies, and made to feel their importance. The Bowne place in Flushing, a
  • 63. very old type of Long Island farm-house, was turned into a museum by the Bowne family itself—an excellent idea. The Quaker Meeting- house in Flushing, though not so old by twenty-five years as it is painted in the sign which says Built in 1695, will probably be preserved as a museum too. An Old House in Flatbush. Another relic in that locality well worth keeping is the Duryea place, a striking old stone farm-house with a wide window on the second floor, now shut in with a wooden cover supported by a long brace-pole reaching to the ground. Out of this window, it is said, a cannon used to point. This was while the house was head-quarters for Hessian officers, during the long monotonous months when the main army of the British army lay at Flushing from Whitestone to Jamaica; and upon Flushing Heights there stood one of the tar- barrel beacons that reached from New York to Norwich Hill, near Oyster Bay. The British officers used to kill time by playing at Fives against the blank wall of the Quaker Meeting-house, or by riding
  • 64. over to Hempstead Plains to the fox-hunts—where the Meadowbrook Hunt Club rides to the hounds to-day. The common soldiers meanwhile stayed in Flushing and amused themselves, according to the same historian, by rolling cannon-balls about a course of nine holes. That was probably the nearest approach to the great game at that time in America, and it may have been played on the site of the present Flushing Golf Club. These same soldiers also amused themselves in less innocent ways, so that the Quakers and other non-combatants in and about this notorious Tory centre used to hide their live stock indoors over night, to keep it from being made into meals by the British. That may account for the habit of the family occupying the Duryea place referred to; they keep their cow in a room at one end of the house. At any rate it is not necessary for New Yorkers to go to Ireland to see sights of that sort. Those are a few of the historic country places that have come to town. There is a surprisingly large number of them, and even when they are not adopted and tableted by the D. A. R. or D. R., or S. R. or S. A. R., they are at least known to local fame, and are pointed out and made much of. But the many abandoned country houses which are not especially historic or significant—except to certain old persons to whom they once meant home—goodly old places, no longer even near the country, but caught by the tide well within the city, that is the kind to be sorry for. Nobody pays much attention to them. A forlorn For Sale sign hangs out in front, weather-beaten and discouraged. The tall Colonial columns still try to stand up straight and to appear unconscious of the faded paint and broken windows, hoping that no one notices the tangle of weeds in the old-fashioned garden, where old-fashioned children used to play hide-and-seek among the box-paths, now overgrown or buried under tin cans.... Across the way, perhaps, there has already squatted an unabashed row of cheap, vulgar houses, impudent, staring little city homes, vividly painted, and all exactly alike, with highly ornamented wooden
  • 65. stoops below and zinc cornices above, like false-hair fronts. They look at times as though they were putting their heads together to gossip and smile about their odd, old neighbor that has such out-of- date fan-lights, that has no electric bell, no folding-beds, and not a bit of zinc cornicing. Meanwhile the old house turns its gaze the other way, thinking of days gone by, patiently waiting the end—which will come soon enough.
  • 66. Transcriber's Notes: Simple typographical errors were corrected. Punctuation and spelling were made consistent when a predominant preference was found in this book; otherwise they were not changed. Page 8, first line: manifestations of the spirit could be or.
  • 67. *** END OF THE PROJECT GUTENBERG EBOOK NEW YORK SKETCHES *** Updated editions will replace the previous one—the old editions will be renamed. Creating the works from print editions not protected by U.S. copyright law means that no one owns a United States copyright in these works, so the Foundation (and you!) can copy and distribute it in the United States without permission and without paying copyright royalties. Special rules, set forth in the General Terms of Use part of this license, apply to copying and distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works to protect the PROJECT GUTENBERG™ concept and trademark. Project Gutenberg is a registered trademark, and may not be used if you charge for an eBook, except by following the terms of the trademark license, including paying royalties for use of the Project Gutenberg trademark. If you do not charge anything for copies of this eBook, complying with the trademark license is very easy. You may use this eBook for nearly any purpose such as creation of derivative works, reports, performances and research. Project Gutenberg eBooks may be modified and printed and given away—you may do practically ANYTHING in the United States with eBooks not protected by U.S. copyright law. Redistribution is subject to the trademark license, especially commercial redistribution. START: FULL LICENSE
  • 68. THE FULL PROJECT GUTENBERG LICENSE
  • 69. PLEASE READ THIS BEFORE YOU DISTRIBUTE OR USE THIS WORK To protect the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting the free distribution of electronic works, by using or distributing this work (or any other work associated in any way with the phrase “Project Gutenberg”), you agree to comply with all the terms of the Full Project Gutenberg™ License available with this file or online at www.gutenberg.org/license. Section 1. General Terms of Use and Redistributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works 1.A. By reading or using any part of this Project Gutenberg™ electronic work, you indicate that you have read, understand, agree to and accept all the terms of this license and intellectual property (trademark/copyright) agreement. If you do not agree to abide by all the terms of this agreement, you must cease using and return or destroy all copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in your possession. If you paid a fee for obtaining a copy of or access to a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work and you do not agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement, you may obtain a refund from the person or entity to whom you paid the fee as set forth in paragraph 1.E.8. 1.B. “Project Gutenberg” is a registered trademark. It may only be used on or associated in any way with an electronic work by people who agree to be bound by the terms of this agreement. There are a few things that you can do with most Project Gutenberg™ electronic works even without complying with the full terms of this agreement. See paragraph 1.C below. There are a lot of things you can do with Project Gutenberg™ electronic works if you follow the terms of this agreement and help preserve free future access to Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. See paragraph 1.E below.
  • 70. 1.C. The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation (“the Foundation” or PGLAF), owns a compilation copyright in the collection of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works. Nearly all the individual works in the collection are in the public domain in the United States. If an individual work is unprotected by copyright law in the United States and you are located in the United States, we do not claim a right to prevent you from copying, distributing, performing, displaying or creating derivative works based on the work as long as all references to Project Gutenberg are removed. Of course, we hope that you will support the Project Gutenberg™ mission of promoting free access to electronic works by freely sharing Project Gutenberg™ works in compliance with the terms of this agreement for keeping the Project Gutenberg™ name associated with the work. You can easily comply with the terms of this agreement by keeping this work in the same format with its attached full Project Gutenberg™ License when you share it without charge with others. 1.D. The copyright laws of the place where you are located also govern what you can do with this work. Copyright laws in most countries are in a constant state of change. If you are outside the United States, check the laws of your country in addition to the terms of this agreement before downloading, copying, displaying, performing, distributing or creating derivative works based on this work or any other Project Gutenberg™ work. The Foundation makes no representations concerning the copyright status of any work in any country other than the United States. 1.E. Unless you have removed all references to Project Gutenberg: 1.E.1. The following sentence, with active links to, or other immediate access to, the full Project Gutenberg™ License must appear prominently whenever any copy of a Project Gutenberg™ work (any work on which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” appears, or with which the phrase “Project Gutenberg” is associated) is accessed, displayed, performed, viewed, copied or distributed:
  • 71. This eBook is for the use of anyone anywhere in the United States and most other parts of the world at no cost and with almost no restrictions whatsoever. You may copy it, give it away or re-use it under the terms of the Project Gutenberg License included with this eBook or online at www.gutenberg.org. If you are not located in the United States, you will have to check the laws of the country where you are located before using this eBook. 1.E.2. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is derived from texts not protected by U.S. copyright law (does not contain a notice indicating that it is posted with permission of the copyright holder), the work can be copied and distributed to anyone in the United States without paying any fees or charges. If you are redistributing or providing access to a work with the phrase “Project Gutenberg” associated with or appearing on the work, you must comply either with the requirements of paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 or obtain permission for the use of the work and the Project Gutenberg™ trademark as set forth in paragraphs 1.E.8 or 1.E.9. 1.E.3. If an individual Project Gutenberg™ electronic work is posted with the permission of the copyright holder, your use and distribution must comply with both paragraphs 1.E.1 through 1.E.7 and any additional terms imposed by the copyright holder. Additional terms will be linked to the Project Gutenberg™ License for all works posted with the permission of the copyright holder found at the beginning of this work. 1.E.4. Do not unlink or detach or remove the full Project Gutenberg™ License terms from this work, or any files containing a part of this work or any other work associated with Project Gutenberg™. 1.E.5. Do not copy, display, perform, distribute or redistribute this electronic work, or any part of this electronic work, without prominently displaying the sentence set forth in paragraph 1.E.1
  • 72. with active links or immediate access to the full terms of the Project Gutenberg™ License. 1.E.6. You may convert to and distribute this work in any binary, compressed, marked up, nonproprietary or proprietary form, including any word processing or hypertext form. However, if you provide access to or distribute copies of a Project Gutenberg™ work in a format other than “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other format used in the official version posted on the official Project Gutenberg™ website (www.gutenberg.org), you must, at no additional cost, fee or expense to the user, provide a copy, a means of exporting a copy, or a means of obtaining a copy upon request, of the work in its original “Plain Vanilla ASCII” or other form. Any alternate format must include the full Project Gutenberg™ License as specified in paragraph 1.E.1. 1.E.7. Do not charge a fee for access to, viewing, displaying, performing, copying or distributing any Project Gutenberg™ works unless you comply with paragraph 1.E.8 or 1.E.9. 1.E.8. You may charge a reasonable fee for copies of or providing access to or distributing Project Gutenberg™ electronic works provided that: • You pay a royalty fee of 20% of the gross profits you derive from the use of Project Gutenberg™ works calculated using the method you already use to calculate your applicable taxes. The fee is owed to the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, but he has agreed to donate royalties under this paragraph to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation. Royalty payments must be paid within 60 days following each date on which you prepare (or are legally required to prepare) your periodic tax returns. Royalty payments should be clearly marked as such and sent to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation at the address specified in Section 4, “Information
  • 73. about donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation.” • You provide a full refund of any money paid by a user who notifies you in writing (or by e-mail) within 30 days of receipt that s/he does not agree to the terms of the full Project Gutenberg™ License. You must require such a user to return or destroy all copies of the works possessed in a physical medium and discontinue all use of and all access to other copies of Project Gutenberg™ works. • You provide, in accordance with paragraph 1.F.3, a full refund of any money paid for a work or a replacement copy, if a defect in the electronic work is discovered and reported to you within 90 days of receipt of the work. • You comply with all other terms of this agreement for free distribution of Project Gutenberg™ works. 1.E.9. If you wish to charge a fee or distribute a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work or group of works on different terms than are set forth in this agreement, you must obtain permission in writing from the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the manager of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark. Contact the Foundation as set forth in Section 3 below. 1.F. 1.F.1. Project Gutenberg volunteers and employees expend considerable effort to identify, do copyright research on, transcribe and proofread works not protected by U.S. copyright law in creating the Project Gutenberg™ collection. Despite these efforts, Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, and the medium on which they may be stored, may contain “Defects,” such as, but not limited to, incomplete, inaccurate or corrupt data, transcription errors, a copyright or other intellectual property infringement, a defective or
  • 74. damaged disk or other medium, a computer virus, or computer codes that damage or cannot be read by your equipment. 1.F.2. LIMITED WARRANTY, DISCLAIMER OF DAMAGES - Except for the “Right of Replacement or Refund” described in paragraph 1.F.3, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, the owner of the Project Gutenberg™ trademark, and any other party distributing a Project Gutenberg™ electronic work under this agreement, disclaim all liability to you for damages, costs and expenses, including legal fees. YOU AGREE THAT YOU HAVE NO REMEDIES FOR NEGLIGENCE, STRICT LIABILITY, BREACH OF WARRANTY OR BREACH OF CONTRACT EXCEPT THOSE PROVIDED IN PARAGRAPH 1.F.3. YOU AGREE THAT THE FOUNDATION, THE TRADEMARK OWNER, AND ANY DISTRIBUTOR UNDER THIS AGREEMENT WILL NOT BE LIABLE TO YOU FOR ACTUAL, DIRECT, INDIRECT, CONSEQUENTIAL, PUNITIVE OR INCIDENTAL DAMAGES EVEN IF YOU GIVE NOTICE OF THE POSSIBILITY OF SUCH DAMAGE. 1.F.3. LIMITED RIGHT OF REPLACEMENT OR REFUND - If you discover a defect in this electronic work within 90 days of receiving it, you can receive a refund of the money (if any) you paid for it by sending a written explanation to the person you received the work from. If you received the work on a physical medium, you must return the medium with your written explanation. The person or entity that provided you with the defective work may elect to provide a replacement copy in lieu of a refund. If you received the work electronically, the person or entity providing it to you may choose to give you a second opportunity to receive the work electronically in lieu of a refund. If the second copy is also defective, you may demand a refund in writing without further opportunities to fix the problem. 1.F.4. Except for the limited right of replacement or refund set forth in paragraph 1.F.3, this work is provided to you ‘AS-IS’, WITH NO OTHER WARRANTIES OF ANY KIND, EXPRESS OR IMPLIED,
  • 75. INCLUDING BUT NOT LIMITED TO WARRANTIES OF MERCHANTABILITY OR FITNESS FOR ANY PURPOSE. 1.F.5. Some states do not allow disclaimers of certain implied warranties or the exclusion or limitation of certain types of damages. If any disclaimer or limitation set forth in this agreement violates the law of the state applicable to this agreement, the agreement shall be interpreted to make the maximum disclaimer or limitation permitted by the applicable state law. The invalidity or unenforceability of any provision of this agreement shall not void the remaining provisions. 1.F.6. INDEMNITY - You agree to indemnify and hold the Foundation, the trademark owner, any agent or employee of the Foundation, anyone providing copies of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works in accordance with this agreement, and any volunteers associated with the production, promotion and distribution of Project Gutenberg™ electronic works, harmless from all liability, costs and expenses, including legal fees, that arise directly or indirectly from any of the following which you do or cause to occur: (a) distribution of this or any Project Gutenberg™ work, (b) alteration, modification, or additions or deletions to any Project Gutenberg™ work, and (c) any Defect you cause. Section 2. Information about the Mission of Project Gutenberg™ Project Gutenberg™ is synonymous with the free distribution of electronic works in formats readable by the widest variety of computers including obsolete, old, middle-aged and new computers. It exists because of the efforts of hundreds of volunteers and donations from people in all walks of life. Volunteers and financial support to provide volunteers with the assistance they need are critical to reaching Project Gutenberg™’s goals and ensuring that the Project Gutenberg™ collection will
  • 76. remain freely available for generations to come. In 2001, the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation was created to provide a secure and permanent future for Project Gutenberg™ and future generations. To learn more about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation and how your efforts and donations can help, see Sections 3 and 4 and the Foundation information page at www.gutenberg.org. Section 3. Information about the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation The Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation is a non-profit 501(c)(3) educational corporation organized under the laws of the state of Mississippi and granted tax exempt status by the Internal Revenue Service. The Foundation’s EIN or federal tax identification number is 64-6221541. Contributions to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation are tax deductible to the full extent permitted by U.S. federal laws and your state’s laws. The Foundation’s business office is located at 809 North 1500 West, Salt Lake City, UT 84116, (801) 596-1887. Email contact links and up to date contact information can be found at the Foundation’s website and official page at www.gutenberg.org/contact Section 4. Information about Donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation Project Gutenberg™ depends upon and cannot survive without widespread public support and donations to carry out its mission of increasing the number of public domain and licensed works that can be freely distributed in machine-readable form accessible by the widest array of equipment including outdated equipment. Many
  • 77. small donations ($1 to $5,000) are particularly important to maintaining tax exempt status with the IRS. The Foundation is committed to complying with the laws regulating charities and charitable donations in all 50 states of the United States. Compliance requirements are not uniform and it takes a considerable effort, much paperwork and many fees to meet and keep up with these requirements. We do not solicit donations in locations where we have not received written confirmation of compliance. To SEND DONATIONS or determine the status of compliance for any particular state visit www.gutenberg.org/donate. While we cannot and do not solicit contributions from states where we have not met the solicitation requirements, we know of no prohibition against accepting unsolicited donations from donors in such states who approach us with offers to donate. International donations are gratefully accepted, but we cannot make any statements concerning tax treatment of donations received from outside the United States. U.S. laws alone swamp our small staff. Please check the Project Gutenberg web pages for current donation methods and addresses. Donations are accepted in a number of other ways including checks, online payments and credit card donations. To donate, please visit: www.gutenberg.org/donate. Section 5. General Information About Project Gutenberg™ electronic works Professor Michael S. Hart was the originator of the Project Gutenberg™ concept of a library of electronic works that could be freely shared with anyone. For forty years, he produced and distributed Project Gutenberg™ eBooks with only a loose network of volunteer support.
  • 78. Project Gutenberg™ eBooks are often created from several printed editions, all of which are confirmed as not protected by copyright in the U.S. unless a copyright notice is included. Thus, we do not necessarily keep eBooks in compliance with any particular paper edition. Most people start at our website which has the main PG search facility: www.gutenberg.org. This website includes information about Project Gutenberg™, including how to make donations to the Project Gutenberg Literary Archive Foundation, how to help produce our new eBooks, and how to subscribe to our email newsletter to hear about new eBooks.
  • 79. Welcome to our website – the perfect destination for book lovers and knowledge seekers. We believe that every book holds a new world, offering opportunities for learning, discovery, and personal growth. That’s why we are dedicated to bringing you a diverse collection of books, ranging from classic literature and specialized publications to self-development guides and children's books. More than just a book-buying platform, we strive to be a bridge connecting you with timeless cultural and intellectual values. With an elegant, user-friendly interface and a smart search system, you can quickly find the books that best suit your interests. Additionally, our special promotions and home delivery services help you save time and fully enjoy the joy of reading. Join us on a journey of knowledge exploration, passion nurturing, and personal growth every day! ebookbell.com