Forthcoming in Proceedings of the Eighth Conference of the International Society for the
Study of Argumentation, ed. B. Garssen, D. Godden, F.S. Henkemans & G. Mitchell
(Amsterdam: Rozenberg Publishers, 2015)
Argument Operators and Hinge Terms in Climate Science
GORDON R. MITCHELL & JOHN LYNE
Department of Communication
University of Pittsburgh
USA
gordonm@pitt.edu; lyne.john@gmail.com
ABSTRACT: Climate scientist James Hansen’s use of we call ‘hinge terms’ — such as ‘dangerous’ and ‘tipping
point’ — operate to reconfigure argumentation on global warming by pre-scripting headlines of media coverage on
scientific findings. Study of this case stands to elucidate an understudied aspect of the global warming controversy,
as well as contribute to understanding of how ‘argument operators’ function to relocate arguments into different
contexts, with potential implications for argumentation theory.
KEYWORDS: global warming, argument activity type, rhetorical figures, James Hansen, rhetoric of science
1. INTRODUCTION
The intellectual roots of American argumentation scholarship intertwine with the tradition of
public address criticism, a fact that helps account for the centrality of context in the work of
prominent American scholars of argument (e.g., Newman 1961; Zarefsky 1990). The recent
launch of the Dutch journal Argumentation in Context, along with a new book series by the same
name, provides an occasion to explore how the American approach to criticism of public
argument in situated contexts relates to new features of pragma-dialectics that emphasize
contextual features of argumentation, such as the concept of “argumentative activity types” (van
Eemeren & Houtlosser 2009).
Considerable attention has been devoted in pragma-dialectics to understanding how
context may “discipline” norms for judging the soundness of arguments that unfold within a
particular argumentative activity type (van Eemeren & Houtlosser 2009, p. 15). Left
understudied, however, is the question of what happens when an argument shifts from one
activity type to another, and further, what moves by interlocutors might spur, or block, such
shifts.
We use the term “argument operators” to refer to detectable moves that change argument
modalities. Our focus here is on operators that relocate arguments within different normative
contexts. While context is featured in various ways within the literature of argumentation (e.g.
fields, argumentation activity types), it is normally taken to be a form of pre-figured ground that
constrains or regulates what is possible within the given context. Our focus differs in that it calls
attention to argumentative strategies that relocate an existing argument within a different context,
thereby changing the norms and constraints that pertain to the argument.1
1
We note that the term “operators,” as defined by computer programming languages, may show some
elemental similarities to the ones we are describing, in that they allow manipulations of “semantic” as well as
2
The specific argument operator that is our concern here is what we call the “hinge term,”
and the case of climate scientist James Hansen’s argumentation on global warming provides an
apt point of departure for our inquiry. The effect of the hinge term, as one type of argument
operator, we contend, is to significantly affect the tenor and trajectory of climate change
arguments. In particular, Hansen’s controversial use of hinge terms such as ‘dangerous’ and
‘tipping point’ in his peer reviewed journal articles operate to pivot his argumentation on global
warming from the context of professional scientific discourse into the context of general public
argument. In what follows, background on the Hansen case (in part two) paves the way for
critical analysis of his strategic deployment of hinge terms (in part three). Part four draws lessons
from the case study to sketch a speculative taxonomy of argument operators and open discussion
about the possible utility of the concept. A concluding section reflects on how our intervention
relates to ongoing work on argument context in pragma-dialectics.
2. FROM RETICENCE TO WITNESSING
Widely considered to be one of the world’s leading climate scientists, James Hansen
began his research career by exploring how particulate matter in the Earth’s atmosphere refracts
light from lunar eclipses (Matsushima, Zink & Hansen 1966). Shortly after completing his Ph.D.
thesis at the University of Iowa, which dealt with properties of Venus’s clouds, Hansen realized
that many of the same dynamics driving changes in Venus’s atmosphere might also be occurring
on Earth. A decade of work from 1978 to 1988 that involved building a complex computer
model of the Earth’s atmosphere led to Hansen’s first major public appearances as a scientist. As
an official witness before the U.S. Congress during 1988 and 1989, Hansen declared with “99
percent confidence” that human carbon dioxide emissions were causing long-term warming in
the Earth’s atmosphere.
Hansen’s bombshell congressional testimony provoked intense controversy and earned
him the moniker “grandfather of climate change”—a role the scientist was not quick to embrace
(McKie 2009). Following his first big splash as a public figure, Hansen (2009) “was firmly
resolved to go back to pure science” and leave media appearances to “people who were more
articulate and seemed to enjoy the process” (p. xvi). This retreat to the laboratory was consistent
with Hansen’s (2007a) perspective on “scientific reticence,” a default rhetorical posture for
scientists that involves a tendency to understate claims and emphasize the uncertain, open-ended
nature of scientific knowledge (see also Ziman 2000).
For nearly a decade following his blockbuster congressional testimony in 1988/1989,
Hansen practiced scientific reticence, publishing findings from his work on Global Circulation
Models in peer reviewed journals and eschewing opportunities to appear in the media spotlight.
Yet that posture changed in 1998, when Hansen agreed to participate in public debates on global
warming with climate “contrarians” Patrick Michaels in New York City, and Richard Lindzen in
Cambridge, Massachusetts (Mitchell & O’Donnell 2000). As Hansen (2009) explained his
motivation for stepping out of the laboratory and into the public square for the first time since his
famous congressional testimony, “I wanted to present and publish a table of the key differences
between my position regarding global warming and the position of the contrarians” (p. xvi).
“syntactic” properties. At present, however, the language of “genre,” “stance,” “audience,” and so on, seem reserved
for natural languages used in non-computational contexts. This is not to say that these could not be represented in
binary code.
3
Hansen’s participation in the New York debate marked a turning point in his career, as
afterward he increasingly embraced the role of a “public witness” to the dangers of global
warming, especially following the birth of his first grandchild in 1999 (Hansen 2009, p. xii). This
path would eventually lead to Hansen’s appearances at rock concerts and protest demonstrations
with climate change activists (Eilperin & Mufson 2013). Also during this period, a subtle shift in
the rhetorical arc of his scientific papers could be detected. For example, in an article published
in Atmospheric Chemistry & Physics, Hansen and colleagues (Hansen et al. 2007a) repeatedly
use the terms ‘tipping point’ and ‘dangerous’ to describe global warming. Major news outlets
parroted those terms in headlines during the news cycle in which the paper was published:
• “Research finds that Earth’s climate is approaching ‘dangerous’ point” (PR
Newswire 2007);
• “NASA Research Suggests Earth climate approaching dangerous point” (Space
Daily 2007);
• “Earth nears tipping point on climate change.” (Spotts 2007)
Messages of danger are part of the stock and trade of newspapers, so Hansen was in effect pre-
scripting headlines for general circulation and pivoting toward a different context and rhetorical
stance. As a scientific argument became a public argument, the assessment of “facts” would
move into a normative environment where questions of “value” and policy response would
predictably arise. This netted Hansen a broader audience, but it complicated his voice as a
scientist. Was he now acting as an advocate?
3. ‘DANGEROUS’ AND ‘TIPPING POINT’ AS HINGE TERMS
By 2007, Hansen had become engaged fully in the rhetorical project of trying to invent ways of
communicating the gravity of what he called the ‘climate catastrophe’ (2007b) to broader
publics. In one open communication on his personal website, he mused:
A related alternative metaphor, perhaps less objectionable while still making the most
basic point, comes to mind in connection with an image of crashing of massive ice sheets
fronts into the sea -- an image of relevance to both climate tipping points and
consequences (sea level rise). Can these crashing glaciers serve as a Krystal Nacht, and
wake us up to the inhumane consequences of averting our eyes? Alas, that metaphor
probably would be greeted with the same reaction from the people who objected to the
first. That reaction may have been spurred by the clever mischaracterization of the CEO,
aiming to achieve just such a reaction. So far that seems to have been the story: the
special interests have been cleverer than us, preventing the public from seeing the crisis
that should be in view. It is hard for me to think of a different equally poignant example
of the foreseeable consequence faced by fellow creatures on the planet. Suggestions are
welcome. (Hansen 2007c)
This candid reflection laid bare for Hansen a fundamental dilemma facing scientists working on
politically charged topics. The tradition of scientific reticence counsels restraint, yet the ethical
calling to bear witness may demand more strident rhetoric. Ultimately, Hansen and colleagues
settled on the terms ‘dangerous’ and ‘tipping point’ as red flags to heighten salience of the issue.
4
While Hansen personally deployed such terms increasingly during public appearances, he also
worked with his co-authors to pepper their scientific papers with these terms. For example, the
previously mentioned Atmospheric Chemistry & Physics paper (Hansen et al. 2007) features 36
mentions of ‘dangerous’ in various contexts (see Table 1).
Table 1. Mentions of “dangerous” in Hansen et al. (2007). References with
quotation marks are in blue, while references without quotation marks are in
red.
Notably, the first four mentions of the term “dangerous” on the paper’s first page are
accompanied by quotation marks, indicating perhaps some hesitance regarding use of the term.
However, in the final five pages of the paper, these quotation marks drop out and dangerous
appears as an unqualified adjective in 9 of 16 instances. In the penultimate discussion section, all
three mentions of dangerous appear without quotations. This progression may reflect a common
tendency of authors to move from a tentative to a more authoritative voice as their papers
5
develop (Fahnestock 1998; Holmes 1997; Peacock 2002; Ruiying & Allison 2003), yet such
maneuvers did not escape the notice of the peer review referees. In an interactive comment
published in Atmospheric Chemistry & Physics Discussions, Hansen and colleagues (2007, p.
S7351) note that referee #1 “expressed mild concern about terms such as ‘dangerous
anthropogenic interference,’ ‘disruptive climate effects,’ and ‘tipping points.’”
Some of this pushback may have stemmed from the sheer number of ‘dangerous’
references in the paper. As Jeanne Fahnestock (1999, pp. 160-172) observes, strategic repetition
of key terms (characterized by the classical rhetorical figure of ploche) can heighten the impact
of scientific argumentation on audiences. Fahnestock points to Charles Darwin’s deployment of
“subtler repetitions that declare identity in reference or the interconnections among phenomena”
to illustrate how ploche can operate to heighten, in the terminology of Perelman and Olbrechts-
Tyteca (1969, p. 144), a scientific argument’s ‘presence.’ Just as Darwin eschewed mere
repetition, instead weaving different meanings through recurrent references, Hansen and
colleagues deploy ‘dangerous’ in an array of different usages, in effect producing a pedagogy of
dangerousness from which journalists could learn.
Previous scholarship has explored some of the rhetorical entailments associated with
Hansen’s use of terms such as ‘tipping point.’ For example, Russill (2008, 2010) notes that in the
global warming controversy, ‘tipping point’ tends to invoke the interests of future generations, as
irreversible, runaway climate change would be most harmful to those not yet born. Yet as Figure
1 illustrates, concepts from the rhetorical tradition furnish a set of transformations that point to
ways that Hansen’s hinge term strategy may carry even broader implications.
Figure 1. Rhetorical concepts illustrate ways that the hinge term ‘dangerous’ enables discourse to swing from
one activity, genre, stasis or stance to another.
As the far left column suggests, successful deployment of the hinge term ‘dangerous’ enables
discourse to swing from the argument activity type of scientific peer review to a different one—
general public argument. In a related transformation, alterations in types of questions asked and
goals pursued by interlocutors are marked by a shift in rhetorical genre. Whereas scientific
discourse tends to follow patterns of reasoning associated with the forensic genre (rooted in the
rhetorical tradition of adjudication in the law courts), public argument tends to feature epideictic
(ceremonial) and deliberative (political decision-making) forms of reasoning (Fahnestock 1998).
As the discourse migrates in this fashion, a further element of transformation occurs at the level
of rhetorical stases, with argumentation “pulled” (Walsh 2010) from stases of fact and definition,
6
into a different stasis point in which interlocutors debate how contingent value judgments relate
to possible future courses of action. Aligned with all of these transformations is a concomitant
shift evident in “rhetorical stance” (Booth 1963), as Hansen himself moves from self-identifying
as a “reticent scientist” to a “public witness.”
4. ARGUMENT OPERATORS: NUDGE, PIVOT, OR JUMP
The Hansen case calls to the fore three possible approaches to context-switching, and the
response to Hansen sorts out to some degree according to which of these the audience senses his
speech acts are aspiring to do. To identify these shifts we use intuitive language—common
verbs, not adjectives—rather than terminology that aims for technical precision. These operators,
we suggest, can do the following:
• Nudge an argument into a wider or narrower context, thereby expanding the range
of rational strictures on relevance (see Walton 2003), but without introducing
competing or conflicting accounts;2
• Pivot strategically between competing or complementary contexts of rational
assessment;
• Jump to an alternative context.
The first two of these may serve as bridges from one context to another, whereas the third
makes a leap. The response to Hansen seems to depend in large part on which of these his
readers are sensing. Being both a scientist and a citizen, Hansen might see his repeated
invocation of the term ‘dangerous’ as a way of nudging his audience into a wider context that
encompasses science but also the field of citizen action. While we do not reject such a
characterization, our analysis picks up on what can be seen as a strategic pivot from one generic
context, with its usual strictures and enablements to another. His critics seem inclined to see
Hansen's performance as a kind of abandonment—jumping ship, so to speak—by violating
constraints of a professional context in order to play out the argument in a different context.
They would no doubt see that characterization underlined by Hansen’s subsequent activism. In
response, Hansen might point to the fact that the term ‘dangerous’ had been utilized previously
in major scientific reports on climate change, and that ‘tipping point’ language was justified
because it “conveys aspects of climate change that have been an impediment to public
appreciation of the urgency of addressing human-caused global warning” (Hansen et al. 2007b,
p. S7351). All of these considerations come to bear as we interrogate the kind of speech acts
Hansen was deploying.
With one foot in the lab and one foot in the public media, it is quite possible that Hansen
could be celebrated as exemplary of the “third culture” figure, who manages to speak
persuasively across the boundaries between fields of expertise and contexts of public argument,
contributing to a culture that consists of both experts and non-experts, and constituted in such a
way that effective participation requires accepting the legitimacy of both empirical and
interpretive methods (Lyne 2010). In that case we would have to see him in a rather different
2
Here we highlight “expansion” rather than shifts, but these are not always distinct, as Burke (1945) points
out in commentary on “scope and reduction” (pp. 59-117).
7
light than some of his critics have. He would be seen as crafting a distinctive voice that bridges,
or “nudges” toward a more encompassing audience.
Because we regard arguments as something more than meaningful texts, we take their
meaning to function in relation to human action. On this approach, the wider investigative terrain
for argument operators is suggested by the speech act vocabulary, following John Searle (1969)
and other speech act theorists (Austin 1975; van Eemeren & Grootendorst 1984), of locution,
illocution, and perlocution which we translate as ways of posing the following general questions:
• Locution: What are you saying?
• Illocution: What are you doing?
• Perlocution: What effect are you having?
As we move down the list, each function presupposes what is listed above. That is, someone
says in order to do in order to have some kind of effect. The last category, perlocution, can be
variously understood as an actual consequence of an illocution, as an intended consequence of an
illocution, or as a rationally foreseeable consequence of an illocution. We do not wish to exclude
any of these from our consideration of ‘argumentative effects,’ that is, of the way speech acts
influence ongoing or subsequent arguments or argumentative moves. Thus, the purview of this
analysis would be possible interactions that can be taken as specifically relevant to an argument,
but it would not include any other kind of effect (e.g. hurt feelings, anger, delight).
In reference to the "hinging" we are looking at here, the hinge effect is performed at all
three levels of the speech act. In saying that conditions are dangerous, Hansen is making a shift
in the argumentative context, with the effect that a number of entanglements—ranging from
genre relevance to contestation of appropriateness—begin to work at once. But the nature of the
shift is such that it can be interpreted in several different and contestable ways (see Figure 2).
Figure 2. Hinge term dynamics. Hinge terms enable arguments to swing between genres and stases, with
associated shifts in the arguer's rhetorical stance, artifact produced and activity type.
Returning to a generic reconstruction of the diagram presented in the previous section, we
see five categories that that appear to move in unison. This, we believe, is why the instance of
deploying a hinge term particularly invites attention. Understood as a speech act, Hansen’s
repeated references to danger would reasonably be taken as a warning. And whether by intention
or not, the illocutionary act of warning within one context has the perlocutionary consequence of
pivoting the argument into another discourse frame. As the warning of danger breaks out of the
confines of the presumptive scientific stasis, it produces a secondary perlocutionary effect of
8
moving from “fact” to “value.” Moreover, the shift of stases has a gravitational pull that brings
changes within each of the other categories (Walsh 2010). The text is now recontextualized as
public argument, where it stirs controversy, and signals differences of genre, stasis, stance, and
artifact. To the consternation of many, the line between science and public controversy begins to
dissolve.
5. SCOPING OUT THE LANDSCAPE
We have argued that the hinge term, in its functional sense, inflects toward, or toggles between,
different registers of argument. What it “means,” in the most robust sense, is therefore what it
does when affirmed or invoked, that is, what it does when introduced by a speech act. What it
does to the argument is something more consequential than a mere figure of speech. In this case,
for instance, the terms “danger” and “tipping point” cannot be sequestered as mere metaphors.
Rather than non-literal flourishes, the introduction of such hinge terms into an argument is a
speech act (or a set of speech acts) with the capacity to move arguments in a different direction,
specifically toward different cognitive, affective, cultural, semiotic, or praxial registers. This can
be done either as a deliberate strategy or an unintended consequence of the introduction of the
term, and its consequences can be both foreseen and unforeseen. One of the consequences in this
case was an inflection toward arguments about the objective limits of science and accusations
that these terms had taken Hansen into a “subjective” frame, where their purchase as scientific
claims were questioned.
In describing argument operators specific to this case, we have introduced strategies of
context-shifting. Beyond the hinge term and related context shifters, this case leads us to
anticipate other argument operators that have different modal functions in argument. Hansen was
criticized for acting as an advocate. If he was acting as an advocate, at what point did that voice
emerge? Was it when he dropped the quotation marks when using the word “dangerous”? Or
were there gradations of his shift, perhaps subtly indicated, and when he engaged in a debate
before academics not in his field? Depending on how that question is answered, his arguments
are likely to be judged by one set of norms or by another. In argumentation literature, we observe
that arguments are generally aligned with the intention of the arguer, and it is assumed that the
arguer has a unitary voice, such that that person could be held responsible for inconsistencies or
implications of the argument they are making. Moreover, we assume that the author’s intentions
are framed with a particular normative context in mind. This would be the standard case of
having a “voice” in an argument.
It is the arguer with the unitary voice that is typically assumed in philosophical
discussions of rationality. The leading advocate of philosophical “inferentialism,” Robert
Brandom, speaks of personal accountability in terms of “scorekeeping,” whereby participants in
an argument constantly track and update the commitments and authorizations made by either
party in order to make explicit the rational purport of any utterance (Brandom 2000). This is a
dynamic way of thinking about argument as process, because it depends on the relationship
between present and past assertions rather than on constructs in isolation. And this is a useful
way of thinking about the trail of assertions as they chain out. But in view of the shifts of
context, voice, and other functions of argument operators that we have been referencing, one
might well ask if it is pragmatic to think of arguments only in terms of verbalized propositions
by philosophically focused interlocutors. To understand the complexity of context and its
relationship to argument, it might be useful to consider whether there are a number of different
9
scoreboards and ways of scoring that are the very things at stake in many arguments (Lyne
2013). Public address scholars, who are observant of the relationship between propositional and
non-propositional features of public argument, as well as the various ways that that rational
arguments may play out, have something to bring to the table in laying out argument operators.
We know arguers modulate the voice they are using to advance an argument, sometimes
by “ventriloquizing” the positions of others, or laying out the position of what another would say
were they in top form. This kind of voicing is perhaps most clearly apparent when a surrogate
stands in for a political candidate in a debate, where the aspiration would be to offer up the
arguments the candidate would or could make. Somewhat differently, a defense attorney makes
the best arguments possible, not because he or she necessarily believes them, but because they
are thought to support the best case that might be made in defense of the client. Other arguments,
we well know, are made “for the sake of argument,” without binding the hands of the arguer. We
might well ask what are the ways of shifting in an out of any given frame of time-binding
accountability.
The formal framing of a staged debate or of a courtroom trial generally eliminates any
ambiguity about whether the arguments presented should be seen as isomorphic with those that
the arguer would be personally and ethically accountable for making. In other cases ambiguity or
confusion can arise, as when arguers shift between or among voices. So it would be worthwhile
to pay attention to indicators of voice shiftings. These might be found in tonal changes, changes
of body language, or stylistic changes—factors that have been of interest to students of public
address but have generally been backgrounded in pragmatic analysis of argument.
We have seen from pragma-dialetics that arguments play out differently in different types
of argumentative activities. Here we are suggesting that even within a given argument activity a
shifting of voice can change the function of an argument. So in addition to context-shifters, other
argument operators may need to be fleshed out. This is among the reasons we believe that the
juncture between public address studies and argument studies may enrich both.
REFERENCES
Austin, J. L. (1975). How to do things with words. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Booth, W. C. (1963). The rhetorical stance. College Composition and Communication, 14, 139-145.
Brandom, R. (2000). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representation, and discursive commitment. Cambridge, MA:
Harvard University Press.
Burke, K. (1945). A grammar of motives. Berkeley: University of California Press.
Eemeren, F. H. van & Grootendorst, R. (1984). Speech acts in argumentative discussions. Dordrecht: Foris.
Eemeren, F. H van & Houtlosser, P. (2009). Strategic maneuvering: Examining argumentation in context. In F. H.
van Eemeren & P. Houtlosser (Eds.), Examining Argumentation in Context (pp. 1-24). Amsterdam: John
Benjamins.
Eilperin, J. & Mufson, S. (2013). Activists arrested at White House protesting Keystone pipeline. Washington Post,
February 13.
Fahnestock, J. (1999). Rhetorical figures in science. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Fahnestock, J. (1998). Accommodating science: The rhetorical life of scientific facts. Written Communication, 15,
330-350.
Hansen, J. E. (2009). Storms of my grandchildren. New York: Bloomsbury Books.
Hansen, J. E. (2007a). Scientific reticence and sea level rise. Environmental Research Letters, 2, 1-6.
Hansen, J. E. (2007b). Climate catastrophe. New Scientist, July 28, 30-34.
Hansen, J. E. (2007c). Averting our eyes. Web communication, November 28. Retrieved from
http://www.columbia.edu/~jeh1/mailings/2007/20071128_AvertingOurEyes.pdf
10
Hansen, J. E., et al. (2007a). Dangerous human made interference with climate: A GISS modelE study. Atmospheric
Chemistry & Physics, 7, 2287-2312.
Hansen, J. E., et al. (2007b). Interactive comment on ‘Dangerous human-made interference with climate: A GISS
modelE study,’ Atmospheric Chemistry and Physics Discussions, 6, S7350-S7354.
Holmes, R. (1997). Genre analysis and the social sciences: An investigation of the structure of research article
discussion sections in three disciplines. English for Specific Purposes, 16, 321-337.
Lyne, J. (2013). Having a whole battery of concepts: Thinking rhetorically about the norms of reason. Social
Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 2(1), 143-148.
Lyne, J. (2010). Rhetoric and the third culture: scientists as arguers and critics. In M. J. Porrovecchio (Ed.),
Reengaging the Prospect of Rhetoric (pp. 113-132). New York: Routledge.
Matsushima, S., Zink, J.R., & Hansen, J.E. (1966). Atmospheric extinction by dust particles as determined from
three-color photometry of the lunar eclipse of 19 December 1964. The Astronomical Journal, 71, 103-110.
Mitchell, G.R. & O’Donnell, T. (2000). Full transcript of inaugural AARST science policy forum, New York Hilton,
Friday 20 November 1998, 7-9 pm. Social Epistemology 14, 131-180.
McKie, R. (2009). ‘We have only four years left to act on climate change—America has to lead. Observer (London),
January 17.
Newman, R. P. (1961). Recognition of Communist China: A study in argument. New York: Macmillan.
Peacock, M. (2002). Communicative moves in the discussion section of research articles. System, 30, 479-497.
Perelman, C. & Olbrechts-Tyteca, L. (1969). The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation. J. Wilkinson and P.
Weaver (Trans.). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press.
PR Newswire (2007). Research finds that Earth’s climate is approaching ‘dangerous’ point. May 31.
Ruiying, Y. & Allison, D. (2003). Research articles in applied linguistics: Moving from results to conclusions.
English for Specific Purposes, 22, 365-385.
Russill, C. (2010). Truth and opinion in climate change discourse: The Gore-Hansen disagreement. Public
Understanding of Science, 20, 796-809.
Russill, C. (2008). Tipping point forewarnings in climate change communication: Some implications of an emerging
trend. Environmental Communication, 2, 133-153.
Searle, J. (1969). Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Space Daily (2007). NASA research suggests Earth climate approaching dangerous point. May 31.
Spotts, P. N. (2007). Earth nears tipping point on climate change. Christian Science Monitor, May 30, 2.
Walsh, L. (2010). Visual strategies for establishing ethos across the ‘is/ought’ divide in the IPCC’s report Climate
Change 2007: Summary for Policy Makers. Poroi, 6, http://dx.doi.org/10.13008/2151-2957.1066
Walton, D. (2003). Relevance in argumentation. London: Routledge.
Zarefsky, D. (1990). Lincoln, Douglas, and slavery: In the crucible of public debate. Chicago: University of
Chicago Press.
Ziman, J. (2000). Are debatable scientific questions debatable? Social Epistemology, 14, 187-199.

More Related Content

PDF
Encoding-decoding-climate-change-communication-Nick-Howlett-2015
DOCX
Debating Global Warming in Media Discussion ForumsStrategie
PDF
Climate change denial and its effect on the scientific community (levandowsky...
PDF
Climate
PDF
A psychossocial approach to understanding underground spaces
PDF
A Cultural Studies Approach To Semantic Instability The Case Of News Transla...
DOC
Abbott Q Paper0102
PDF
Environmental Sociology.pdf bs English language and liter
Encoding-decoding-climate-change-communication-Nick-Howlett-2015
Debating Global Warming in Media Discussion ForumsStrategie
Climate change denial and its effect on the scientific community (levandowsky...
Climate
A psychossocial approach to understanding underground spaces
A Cultural Studies Approach To Semantic Instability The Case Of News Transla...
Abbott Q Paper0102
Environmental Sociology.pdf bs English language and liter

Similar to Argument Operators And Hinge Terms In Climate Science (20)

PDF
Introduction to Environmental Sociology.pdf
PDF
Event Arguments Foundations And Applications Reprint 2011 Ed Claudia Maienborn
PDF
Squaring the circle? Some thoughts on the idea of sustainable development
DOCX
Global Warming Persuasive Essay Sample
PPTX
The Visual Framing of the Three Cycles of Climate Control in the New York Tie...
PDF
The Science And Politics Of Global Climate Change A Guide To The Debate 2nd E...
DOCX
Social Problems Perspectives, Disaster Research and Em.docx
PDF
Essay On Gender Discrimination.pdf
PDF
A study of the causes of climate change - a master’s thesis in philosophy of ...
DOCX
Climate change and its skeptics (PAPER)
DOCX
Disasters, 2003, 27(4) 319–335 © Overseas Development Ins.docx
PDF
Text 9 2012 general
PDF
Text 9 2012 general
PDF
Constructing Quantum Mechanics, Volume Two. The Arch: 1903‒1927 1st Edition A...
PDF
2015 Dresden Mandelbrot's other route to1 over f
PDF
Activity And Evaluation Reporting Practices In Academic Writing
PDF
01 multimodal text-analysis-o'halloran_and_smith
PDF
01 multimodal text-analysis-o'halloran_and_smith
DOCX
The accidental career of a symbolic interactionist: How opportunities, not in...
PDF
Introduction To Modern Climate Change 3rd Edition 3rd Andrew E Dessler
Introduction to Environmental Sociology.pdf
Event Arguments Foundations And Applications Reprint 2011 Ed Claudia Maienborn
Squaring the circle? Some thoughts on the idea of sustainable development
Global Warming Persuasive Essay Sample
The Visual Framing of the Three Cycles of Climate Control in the New York Tie...
The Science And Politics Of Global Climate Change A Guide To The Debate 2nd E...
Social Problems Perspectives, Disaster Research and Em.docx
Essay On Gender Discrimination.pdf
A study of the causes of climate change - a master’s thesis in philosophy of ...
Climate change and its skeptics (PAPER)
Disasters, 2003, 27(4) 319–335 © Overseas Development Ins.docx
Text 9 2012 general
Text 9 2012 general
Constructing Quantum Mechanics, Volume Two. The Arch: 1903‒1927 1st Edition A...
2015 Dresden Mandelbrot's other route to1 over f
Activity And Evaluation Reporting Practices In Academic Writing
01 multimodal text-analysis-o'halloran_and_smith
01 multimodal text-analysis-o'halloran_and_smith
The accidental career of a symbolic interactionist: How opportunities, not in...
Introduction To Modern Climate Change 3rd Edition 3rd Andrew E Dessler
Ad

More from Pedro Craggett (20)

PDF
Pay Someone To Write My Paper A Trusted Service
PDF
45 Perfect Thesis Statement Temp
PDF
I Need An Example Of A Reflective Journal - Five B
PDF
Argumentative Writing Sentence Starters By Sam
PDF
020 Narrative Essay Example College Personal
PDF
Pin On Essay Planning Tools
PDF
Explanatory Essay Example Recent Posts
PDF
How To Write A Compare And Contrast Essay Introd
PDF
FREE 9 Sample Essay Templates In MS Word PDF
PDF
Steps For Writing An Essay - ESL Work
PDF
Image Result For Structure Of Discussion Scientific Paper
PDF
Essay Writing Samples
PDF
6 Best Images Of Free Printable Dott
PDF
My School Essay In English Write Essay On My School In English My ...
PDF
Handwriting Worksheets Free Printable
PDF
English Writing 1. Guided Writing In English (Basic E
PDF
Alternative Learning System (ALS) Program Graduates And Level Of Readiness To...
PDF
Adventures Of Huckleberry Finn (Tom Sawyer S Comrade)
PDF
Adolescence And The Risk Of Stereotypes Real Women Have Curves (2002)
PDF
A Compilation Of UAV Applications For Precision Agriculture
Pay Someone To Write My Paper A Trusted Service
45 Perfect Thesis Statement Temp
I Need An Example Of A Reflective Journal - Five B
Argumentative Writing Sentence Starters By Sam
020 Narrative Essay Example College Personal
Pin On Essay Planning Tools
Explanatory Essay Example Recent Posts
How To Write A Compare And Contrast Essay Introd
FREE 9 Sample Essay Templates In MS Word PDF
Steps For Writing An Essay - ESL Work
Image Result For Structure Of Discussion Scientific Paper
Essay Writing Samples
6 Best Images Of Free Printable Dott
My School Essay In English Write Essay On My School In English My ...
Handwriting Worksheets Free Printable
English Writing 1. Guided Writing In English (Basic E
Alternative Learning System (ALS) Program Graduates And Level Of Readiness To...
Adventures Of Huckleberry Finn (Tom Sawyer S Comrade)
Adolescence And The Risk Of Stereotypes Real Women Have Curves (2002)
A Compilation Of UAV Applications For Precision Agriculture
Ad

Recently uploaded (20)

PDF
AI-driven educational solutions for real-life interventions in the Philippine...
PPTX
Unit 4 Computer Architecture Multicore Processor.pptx
PPTX
Share_Module_2_Power_conflict_and_negotiation.pptx
PDF
CISA (Certified Information Systems Auditor) Domain-Wise Summary.pdf
PDF
medical_surgical_nursing_10th_edition_ignatavicius_TEST_BANK_pdf.pdf
PDF
1.3 FINAL REVISED K-10 PE and Health CG 2023 Grades 4-10 (1).pdf
PDF
HVAC Specification 2024 according to central public works department
PDF
semiconductor packaging in vlsi design fab
PDF
Mucosal Drug Delivery system_NDDS_BPHARMACY__SEM VII_PCI.pdf
PDF
ChatGPT for Dummies - Pam Baker Ccesa007.pdf
PDF
BP 704 T. NOVEL DRUG DELIVERY SYSTEMS (UNIT 1)
PDF
Skin Care and Cosmetic Ingredients Dictionary ( PDFDrive ).pdf
PDF
Paper A Mock Exam 9_ Attempt review.pdf.
PDF
International_Financial_Reporting_Standa.pdf
PDF
Uderstanding digital marketing and marketing stratergie for engaging the digi...
PDF
BP 505 T. PHARMACEUTICAL JURISPRUDENCE (UNIT 2).pdf
PDF
Empowerment Technology for Senior High School Guide
PDF
English Textual Question & Ans (12th Class).pdf
PDF
FORM 1 BIOLOGY MIND MAPS and their schemes
PPTX
Introduction to pro and eukaryotes and differences.pptx
AI-driven educational solutions for real-life interventions in the Philippine...
Unit 4 Computer Architecture Multicore Processor.pptx
Share_Module_2_Power_conflict_and_negotiation.pptx
CISA (Certified Information Systems Auditor) Domain-Wise Summary.pdf
medical_surgical_nursing_10th_edition_ignatavicius_TEST_BANK_pdf.pdf
1.3 FINAL REVISED K-10 PE and Health CG 2023 Grades 4-10 (1).pdf
HVAC Specification 2024 according to central public works department
semiconductor packaging in vlsi design fab
Mucosal Drug Delivery system_NDDS_BPHARMACY__SEM VII_PCI.pdf
ChatGPT for Dummies - Pam Baker Ccesa007.pdf
BP 704 T. NOVEL DRUG DELIVERY SYSTEMS (UNIT 1)
Skin Care and Cosmetic Ingredients Dictionary ( PDFDrive ).pdf
Paper A Mock Exam 9_ Attempt review.pdf.
International_Financial_Reporting_Standa.pdf
Uderstanding digital marketing and marketing stratergie for engaging the digi...
BP 505 T. PHARMACEUTICAL JURISPRUDENCE (UNIT 2).pdf
Empowerment Technology for Senior High School Guide
English Textual Question & Ans (12th Class).pdf
FORM 1 BIOLOGY MIND MAPS and their schemes
Introduction to pro and eukaryotes and differences.pptx

Argument Operators And Hinge Terms In Climate Science

  • 1. Forthcoming in Proceedings of the Eighth Conference of the International Society for the Study of Argumentation, ed. B. Garssen, D. Godden, F.S. Henkemans & G. Mitchell (Amsterdam: Rozenberg Publishers, 2015) Argument Operators and Hinge Terms in Climate Science GORDON R. MITCHELL & JOHN LYNE Department of Communication University of Pittsburgh USA gordonm@pitt.edu; lyne.john@gmail.com ABSTRACT: Climate scientist James Hansen’s use of we call ‘hinge terms’ — such as ‘dangerous’ and ‘tipping point’ — operate to reconfigure argumentation on global warming by pre-scripting headlines of media coverage on scientific findings. Study of this case stands to elucidate an understudied aspect of the global warming controversy, as well as contribute to understanding of how ‘argument operators’ function to relocate arguments into different contexts, with potential implications for argumentation theory. KEYWORDS: global warming, argument activity type, rhetorical figures, James Hansen, rhetoric of science 1. INTRODUCTION The intellectual roots of American argumentation scholarship intertwine with the tradition of public address criticism, a fact that helps account for the centrality of context in the work of prominent American scholars of argument (e.g., Newman 1961; Zarefsky 1990). The recent launch of the Dutch journal Argumentation in Context, along with a new book series by the same name, provides an occasion to explore how the American approach to criticism of public argument in situated contexts relates to new features of pragma-dialectics that emphasize contextual features of argumentation, such as the concept of “argumentative activity types” (van Eemeren & Houtlosser 2009). Considerable attention has been devoted in pragma-dialectics to understanding how context may “discipline” norms for judging the soundness of arguments that unfold within a particular argumentative activity type (van Eemeren & Houtlosser 2009, p. 15). Left understudied, however, is the question of what happens when an argument shifts from one activity type to another, and further, what moves by interlocutors might spur, or block, such shifts. We use the term “argument operators” to refer to detectable moves that change argument modalities. Our focus here is on operators that relocate arguments within different normative contexts. While context is featured in various ways within the literature of argumentation (e.g. fields, argumentation activity types), it is normally taken to be a form of pre-figured ground that constrains or regulates what is possible within the given context. Our focus differs in that it calls attention to argumentative strategies that relocate an existing argument within a different context, thereby changing the norms and constraints that pertain to the argument.1 1 We note that the term “operators,” as defined by computer programming languages, may show some elemental similarities to the ones we are describing, in that they allow manipulations of “semantic” as well as
  • 2. 2 The specific argument operator that is our concern here is what we call the “hinge term,” and the case of climate scientist James Hansen’s argumentation on global warming provides an apt point of departure for our inquiry. The effect of the hinge term, as one type of argument operator, we contend, is to significantly affect the tenor and trajectory of climate change arguments. In particular, Hansen’s controversial use of hinge terms such as ‘dangerous’ and ‘tipping point’ in his peer reviewed journal articles operate to pivot his argumentation on global warming from the context of professional scientific discourse into the context of general public argument. In what follows, background on the Hansen case (in part two) paves the way for critical analysis of his strategic deployment of hinge terms (in part three). Part four draws lessons from the case study to sketch a speculative taxonomy of argument operators and open discussion about the possible utility of the concept. A concluding section reflects on how our intervention relates to ongoing work on argument context in pragma-dialectics. 2. FROM RETICENCE TO WITNESSING Widely considered to be one of the world’s leading climate scientists, James Hansen began his research career by exploring how particulate matter in the Earth’s atmosphere refracts light from lunar eclipses (Matsushima, Zink & Hansen 1966). Shortly after completing his Ph.D. thesis at the University of Iowa, which dealt with properties of Venus’s clouds, Hansen realized that many of the same dynamics driving changes in Venus’s atmosphere might also be occurring on Earth. A decade of work from 1978 to 1988 that involved building a complex computer model of the Earth’s atmosphere led to Hansen’s first major public appearances as a scientist. As an official witness before the U.S. Congress during 1988 and 1989, Hansen declared with “99 percent confidence” that human carbon dioxide emissions were causing long-term warming in the Earth’s atmosphere. Hansen’s bombshell congressional testimony provoked intense controversy and earned him the moniker “grandfather of climate change”—a role the scientist was not quick to embrace (McKie 2009). Following his first big splash as a public figure, Hansen (2009) “was firmly resolved to go back to pure science” and leave media appearances to “people who were more articulate and seemed to enjoy the process” (p. xvi). This retreat to the laboratory was consistent with Hansen’s (2007a) perspective on “scientific reticence,” a default rhetorical posture for scientists that involves a tendency to understate claims and emphasize the uncertain, open-ended nature of scientific knowledge (see also Ziman 2000). For nearly a decade following his blockbuster congressional testimony in 1988/1989, Hansen practiced scientific reticence, publishing findings from his work on Global Circulation Models in peer reviewed journals and eschewing opportunities to appear in the media spotlight. Yet that posture changed in 1998, when Hansen agreed to participate in public debates on global warming with climate “contrarians” Patrick Michaels in New York City, and Richard Lindzen in Cambridge, Massachusetts (Mitchell & O’Donnell 2000). As Hansen (2009) explained his motivation for stepping out of the laboratory and into the public square for the first time since his famous congressional testimony, “I wanted to present and publish a table of the key differences between my position regarding global warming and the position of the contrarians” (p. xvi). “syntactic” properties. At present, however, the language of “genre,” “stance,” “audience,” and so on, seem reserved for natural languages used in non-computational contexts. This is not to say that these could not be represented in binary code.
  • 3. 3 Hansen’s participation in the New York debate marked a turning point in his career, as afterward he increasingly embraced the role of a “public witness” to the dangers of global warming, especially following the birth of his first grandchild in 1999 (Hansen 2009, p. xii). This path would eventually lead to Hansen’s appearances at rock concerts and protest demonstrations with climate change activists (Eilperin & Mufson 2013). Also during this period, a subtle shift in the rhetorical arc of his scientific papers could be detected. For example, in an article published in Atmospheric Chemistry & Physics, Hansen and colleagues (Hansen et al. 2007a) repeatedly use the terms ‘tipping point’ and ‘dangerous’ to describe global warming. Major news outlets parroted those terms in headlines during the news cycle in which the paper was published: • “Research finds that Earth’s climate is approaching ‘dangerous’ point” (PR Newswire 2007); • “NASA Research Suggests Earth climate approaching dangerous point” (Space Daily 2007); • “Earth nears tipping point on climate change.” (Spotts 2007) Messages of danger are part of the stock and trade of newspapers, so Hansen was in effect pre- scripting headlines for general circulation and pivoting toward a different context and rhetorical stance. As a scientific argument became a public argument, the assessment of “facts” would move into a normative environment where questions of “value” and policy response would predictably arise. This netted Hansen a broader audience, but it complicated his voice as a scientist. Was he now acting as an advocate? 3. ‘DANGEROUS’ AND ‘TIPPING POINT’ AS HINGE TERMS By 2007, Hansen had become engaged fully in the rhetorical project of trying to invent ways of communicating the gravity of what he called the ‘climate catastrophe’ (2007b) to broader publics. In one open communication on his personal website, he mused: A related alternative metaphor, perhaps less objectionable while still making the most basic point, comes to mind in connection with an image of crashing of massive ice sheets fronts into the sea -- an image of relevance to both climate tipping points and consequences (sea level rise). Can these crashing glaciers serve as a Krystal Nacht, and wake us up to the inhumane consequences of averting our eyes? Alas, that metaphor probably would be greeted with the same reaction from the people who objected to the first. That reaction may have been spurred by the clever mischaracterization of the CEO, aiming to achieve just such a reaction. So far that seems to have been the story: the special interests have been cleverer than us, preventing the public from seeing the crisis that should be in view. It is hard for me to think of a different equally poignant example of the foreseeable consequence faced by fellow creatures on the planet. Suggestions are welcome. (Hansen 2007c) This candid reflection laid bare for Hansen a fundamental dilemma facing scientists working on politically charged topics. The tradition of scientific reticence counsels restraint, yet the ethical calling to bear witness may demand more strident rhetoric. Ultimately, Hansen and colleagues settled on the terms ‘dangerous’ and ‘tipping point’ as red flags to heighten salience of the issue.
  • 4. 4 While Hansen personally deployed such terms increasingly during public appearances, he also worked with his co-authors to pepper their scientific papers with these terms. For example, the previously mentioned Atmospheric Chemistry & Physics paper (Hansen et al. 2007) features 36 mentions of ‘dangerous’ in various contexts (see Table 1). Table 1. Mentions of “dangerous” in Hansen et al. (2007). References with quotation marks are in blue, while references without quotation marks are in red. Notably, the first four mentions of the term “dangerous” on the paper’s first page are accompanied by quotation marks, indicating perhaps some hesitance regarding use of the term. However, in the final five pages of the paper, these quotation marks drop out and dangerous appears as an unqualified adjective in 9 of 16 instances. In the penultimate discussion section, all three mentions of dangerous appear without quotations. This progression may reflect a common tendency of authors to move from a tentative to a more authoritative voice as their papers
  • 5. 5 develop (Fahnestock 1998; Holmes 1997; Peacock 2002; Ruiying & Allison 2003), yet such maneuvers did not escape the notice of the peer review referees. In an interactive comment published in Atmospheric Chemistry & Physics Discussions, Hansen and colleagues (2007, p. S7351) note that referee #1 “expressed mild concern about terms such as ‘dangerous anthropogenic interference,’ ‘disruptive climate effects,’ and ‘tipping points.’” Some of this pushback may have stemmed from the sheer number of ‘dangerous’ references in the paper. As Jeanne Fahnestock (1999, pp. 160-172) observes, strategic repetition of key terms (characterized by the classical rhetorical figure of ploche) can heighten the impact of scientific argumentation on audiences. Fahnestock points to Charles Darwin’s deployment of “subtler repetitions that declare identity in reference or the interconnections among phenomena” to illustrate how ploche can operate to heighten, in the terminology of Perelman and Olbrechts- Tyteca (1969, p. 144), a scientific argument’s ‘presence.’ Just as Darwin eschewed mere repetition, instead weaving different meanings through recurrent references, Hansen and colleagues deploy ‘dangerous’ in an array of different usages, in effect producing a pedagogy of dangerousness from which journalists could learn. Previous scholarship has explored some of the rhetorical entailments associated with Hansen’s use of terms such as ‘tipping point.’ For example, Russill (2008, 2010) notes that in the global warming controversy, ‘tipping point’ tends to invoke the interests of future generations, as irreversible, runaway climate change would be most harmful to those not yet born. Yet as Figure 1 illustrates, concepts from the rhetorical tradition furnish a set of transformations that point to ways that Hansen’s hinge term strategy may carry even broader implications. Figure 1. Rhetorical concepts illustrate ways that the hinge term ‘dangerous’ enables discourse to swing from one activity, genre, stasis or stance to another. As the far left column suggests, successful deployment of the hinge term ‘dangerous’ enables discourse to swing from the argument activity type of scientific peer review to a different one— general public argument. In a related transformation, alterations in types of questions asked and goals pursued by interlocutors are marked by a shift in rhetorical genre. Whereas scientific discourse tends to follow patterns of reasoning associated with the forensic genre (rooted in the rhetorical tradition of adjudication in the law courts), public argument tends to feature epideictic (ceremonial) and deliberative (political decision-making) forms of reasoning (Fahnestock 1998). As the discourse migrates in this fashion, a further element of transformation occurs at the level of rhetorical stases, with argumentation “pulled” (Walsh 2010) from stases of fact and definition,
  • 6. 6 into a different stasis point in which interlocutors debate how contingent value judgments relate to possible future courses of action. Aligned with all of these transformations is a concomitant shift evident in “rhetorical stance” (Booth 1963), as Hansen himself moves from self-identifying as a “reticent scientist” to a “public witness.” 4. ARGUMENT OPERATORS: NUDGE, PIVOT, OR JUMP The Hansen case calls to the fore three possible approaches to context-switching, and the response to Hansen sorts out to some degree according to which of these the audience senses his speech acts are aspiring to do. To identify these shifts we use intuitive language—common verbs, not adjectives—rather than terminology that aims for technical precision. These operators, we suggest, can do the following: • Nudge an argument into a wider or narrower context, thereby expanding the range of rational strictures on relevance (see Walton 2003), but without introducing competing or conflicting accounts;2 • Pivot strategically between competing or complementary contexts of rational assessment; • Jump to an alternative context. The first two of these may serve as bridges from one context to another, whereas the third makes a leap. The response to Hansen seems to depend in large part on which of these his readers are sensing. Being both a scientist and a citizen, Hansen might see his repeated invocation of the term ‘dangerous’ as a way of nudging his audience into a wider context that encompasses science but also the field of citizen action. While we do not reject such a characterization, our analysis picks up on what can be seen as a strategic pivot from one generic context, with its usual strictures and enablements to another. His critics seem inclined to see Hansen's performance as a kind of abandonment—jumping ship, so to speak—by violating constraints of a professional context in order to play out the argument in a different context. They would no doubt see that characterization underlined by Hansen’s subsequent activism. In response, Hansen might point to the fact that the term ‘dangerous’ had been utilized previously in major scientific reports on climate change, and that ‘tipping point’ language was justified because it “conveys aspects of climate change that have been an impediment to public appreciation of the urgency of addressing human-caused global warning” (Hansen et al. 2007b, p. S7351). All of these considerations come to bear as we interrogate the kind of speech acts Hansen was deploying. With one foot in the lab and one foot in the public media, it is quite possible that Hansen could be celebrated as exemplary of the “third culture” figure, who manages to speak persuasively across the boundaries between fields of expertise and contexts of public argument, contributing to a culture that consists of both experts and non-experts, and constituted in such a way that effective participation requires accepting the legitimacy of both empirical and interpretive methods (Lyne 2010). In that case we would have to see him in a rather different 2 Here we highlight “expansion” rather than shifts, but these are not always distinct, as Burke (1945) points out in commentary on “scope and reduction” (pp. 59-117).
  • 7. 7 light than some of his critics have. He would be seen as crafting a distinctive voice that bridges, or “nudges” toward a more encompassing audience. Because we regard arguments as something more than meaningful texts, we take their meaning to function in relation to human action. On this approach, the wider investigative terrain for argument operators is suggested by the speech act vocabulary, following John Searle (1969) and other speech act theorists (Austin 1975; van Eemeren & Grootendorst 1984), of locution, illocution, and perlocution which we translate as ways of posing the following general questions: • Locution: What are you saying? • Illocution: What are you doing? • Perlocution: What effect are you having? As we move down the list, each function presupposes what is listed above. That is, someone says in order to do in order to have some kind of effect. The last category, perlocution, can be variously understood as an actual consequence of an illocution, as an intended consequence of an illocution, or as a rationally foreseeable consequence of an illocution. We do not wish to exclude any of these from our consideration of ‘argumentative effects,’ that is, of the way speech acts influence ongoing or subsequent arguments or argumentative moves. Thus, the purview of this analysis would be possible interactions that can be taken as specifically relevant to an argument, but it would not include any other kind of effect (e.g. hurt feelings, anger, delight). In reference to the "hinging" we are looking at here, the hinge effect is performed at all three levels of the speech act. In saying that conditions are dangerous, Hansen is making a shift in the argumentative context, with the effect that a number of entanglements—ranging from genre relevance to contestation of appropriateness—begin to work at once. But the nature of the shift is such that it can be interpreted in several different and contestable ways (see Figure 2). Figure 2. Hinge term dynamics. Hinge terms enable arguments to swing between genres and stases, with associated shifts in the arguer's rhetorical stance, artifact produced and activity type. Returning to a generic reconstruction of the diagram presented in the previous section, we see five categories that that appear to move in unison. This, we believe, is why the instance of deploying a hinge term particularly invites attention. Understood as a speech act, Hansen’s repeated references to danger would reasonably be taken as a warning. And whether by intention or not, the illocutionary act of warning within one context has the perlocutionary consequence of pivoting the argument into another discourse frame. As the warning of danger breaks out of the confines of the presumptive scientific stasis, it produces a secondary perlocutionary effect of
  • 8. 8 moving from “fact” to “value.” Moreover, the shift of stases has a gravitational pull that brings changes within each of the other categories (Walsh 2010). The text is now recontextualized as public argument, where it stirs controversy, and signals differences of genre, stasis, stance, and artifact. To the consternation of many, the line between science and public controversy begins to dissolve. 5. SCOPING OUT THE LANDSCAPE We have argued that the hinge term, in its functional sense, inflects toward, or toggles between, different registers of argument. What it “means,” in the most robust sense, is therefore what it does when affirmed or invoked, that is, what it does when introduced by a speech act. What it does to the argument is something more consequential than a mere figure of speech. In this case, for instance, the terms “danger” and “tipping point” cannot be sequestered as mere metaphors. Rather than non-literal flourishes, the introduction of such hinge terms into an argument is a speech act (or a set of speech acts) with the capacity to move arguments in a different direction, specifically toward different cognitive, affective, cultural, semiotic, or praxial registers. This can be done either as a deliberate strategy or an unintended consequence of the introduction of the term, and its consequences can be both foreseen and unforeseen. One of the consequences in this case was an inflection toward arguments about the objective limits of science and accusations that these terms had taken Hansen into a “subjective” frame, where their purchase as scientific claims were questioned. In describing argument operators specific to this case, we have introduced strategies of context-shifting. Beyond the hinge term and related context shifters, this case leads us to anticipate other argument operators that have different modal functions in argument. Hansen was criticized for acting as an advocate. If he was acting as an advocate, at what point did that voice emerge? Was it when he dropped the quotation marks when using the word “dangerous”? Or were there gradations of his shift, perhaps subtly indicated, and when he engaged in a debate before academics not in his field? Depending on how that question is answered, his arguments are likely to be judged by one set of norms or by another. In argumentation literature, we observe that arguments are generally aligned with the intention of the arguer, and it is assumed that the arguer has a unitary voice, such that that person could be held responsible for inconsistencies or implications of the argument they are making. Moreover, we assume that the author’s intentions are framed with a particular normative context in mind. This would be the standard case of having a “voice” in an argument. It is the arguer with the unitary voice that is typically assumed in philosophical discussions of rationality. The leading advocate of philosophical “inferentialism,” Robert Brandom, speaks of personal accountability in terms of “scorekeeping,” whereby participants in an argument constantly track and update the commitments and authorizations made by either party in order to make explicit the rational purport of any utterance (Brandom 2000). This is a dynamic way of thinking about argument as process, because it depends on the relationship between present and past assertions rather than on constructs in isolation. And this is a useful way of thinking about the trail of assertions as they chain out. But in view of the shifts of context, voice, and other functions of argument operators that we have been referencing, one might well ask if it is pragmatic to think of arguments only in terms of verbalized propositions by philosophically focused interlocutors. To understand the complexity of context and its relationship to argument, it might be useful to consider whether there are a number of different
  • 9. 9 scoreboards and ways of scoring that are the very things at stake in many arguments (Lyne 2013). Public address scholars, who are observant of the relationship between propositional and non-propositional features of public argument, as well as the various ways that that rational arguments may play out, have something to bring to the table in laying out argument operators. We know arguers modulate the voice they are using to advance an argument, sometimes by “ventriloquizing” the positions of others, or laying out the position of what another would say were they in top form. This kind of voicing is perhaps most clearly apparent when a surrogate stands in for a political candidate in a debate, where the aspiration would be to offer up the arguments the candidate would or could make. Somewhat differently, a defense attorney makes the best arguments possible, not because he or she necessarily believes them, but because they are thought to support the best case that might be made in defense of the client. Other arguments, we well know, are made “for the sake of argument,” without binding the hands of the arguer. We might well ask what are the ways of shifting in an out of any given frame of time-binding accountability. The formal framing of a staged debate or of a courtroom trial generally eliminates any ambiguity about whether the arguments presented should be seen as isomorphic with those that the arguer would be personally and ethically accountable for making. In other cases ambiguity or confusion can arise, as when arguers shift between or among voices. So it would be worthwhile to pay attention to indicators of voice shiftings. These might be found in tonal changes, changes of body language, or stylistic changes—factors that have been of interest to students of public address but have generally been backgrounded in pragmatic analysis of argument. We have seen from pragma-dialetics that arguments play out differently in different types of argumentative activities. Here we are suggesting that even within a given argument activity a shifting of voice can change the function of an argument. So in addition to context-shifters, other argument operators may need to be fleshed out. This is among the reasons we believe that the juncture between public address studies and argument studies may enrich both. REFERENCES Austin, J. L. (1975). How to do things with words. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Booth, W. C. (1963). The rhetorical stance. College Composition and Communication, 14, 139-145. Brandom, R. (2000). Making it explicit: Reasoning, representation, and discursive commitment. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press. Burke, K. (1945). A grammar of motives. Berkeley: University of California Press. Eemeren, F. H. van & Grootendorst, R. (1984). Speech acts in argumentative discussions. Dordrecht: Foris. Eemeren, F. H van & Houtlosser, P. (2009). Strategic maneuvering: Examining argumentation in context. In F. H. van Eemeren & P. Houtlosser (Eds.), Examining Argumentation in Context (pp. 1-24). Amsterdam: John Benjamins. Eilperin, J. & Mufson, S. (2013). Activists arrested at White House protesting Keystone pipeline. Washington Post, February 13. Fahnestock, J. (1999). Rhetorical figures in science. Oxford: Oxford University Press. Fahnestock, J. (1998). Accommodating science: The rhetorical life of scientific facts. Written Communication, 15, 330-350. Hansen, J. E. (2009). Storms of my grandchildren. New York: Bloomsbury Books. Hansen, J. E. (2007a). Scientific reticence and sea level rise. Environmental Research Letters, 2, 1-6. Hansen, J. E. (2007b). Climate catastrophe. New Scientist, July 28, 30-34. Hansen, J. E. (2007c). Averting our eyes. Web communication, November 28. Retrieved from http://www.columbia.edu/~jeh1/mailings/2007/20071128_AvertingOurEyes.pdf
  • 10. 10 Hansen, J. E., et al. (2007a). Dangerous human made interference with climate: A GISS modelE study. Atmospheric Chemistry & Physics, 7, 2287-2312. Hansen, J. E., et al. (2007b). Interactive comment on ‘Dangerous human-made interference with climate: A GISS modelE study,’ Atmospheric Chemistry and Physics Discussions, 6, S7350-S7354. Holmes, R. (1997). Genre analysis and the social sciences: An investigation of the structure of research article discussion sections in three disciplines. English for Specific Purposes, 16, 321-337. Lyne, J. (2013). Having a whole battery of concepts: Thinking rhetorically about the norms of reason. Social Epistemology Review and Reply Collective, 2(1), 143-148. Lyne, J. (2010). Rhetoric and the third culture: scientists as arguers and critics. In M. J. Porrovecchio (Ed.), Reengaging the Prospect of Rhetoric (pp. 113-132). New York: Routledge. Matsushima, S., Zink, J.R., & Hansen, J.E. (1966). Atmospheric extinction by dust particles as determined from three-color photometry of the lunar eclipse of 19 December 1964. The Astronomical Journal, 71, 103-110. Mitchell, G.R. & O’Donnell, T. (2000). Full transcript of inaugural AARST science policy forum, New York Hilton, Friday 20 November 1998, 7-9 pm. Social Epistemology 14, 131-180. McKie, R. (2009). ‘We have only four years left to act on climate change—America has to lead. Observer (London), January 17. Newman, R. P. (1961). Recognition of Communist China: A study in argument. New York: Macmillan. Peacock, M. (2002). Communicative moves in the discussion section of research articles. System, 30, 479-497. Perelman, C. & Olbrechts-Tyteca, L. (1969). The new rhetoric: A treatise on argumentation. J. Wilkinson and P. Weaver (Trans.). Notre Dame: University of Notre Dame Press. PR Newswire (2007). Research finds that Earth’s climate is approaching ‘dangerous’ point. May 31. Ruiying, Y. & Allison, D. (2003). Research articles in applied linguistics: Moving from results to conclusions. English for Specific Purposes, 22, 365-385. Russill, C. (2010). Truth and opinion in climate change discourse: The Gore-Hansen disagreement. Public Understanding of Science, 20, 796-809. Russill, C. (2008). Tipping point forewarnings in climate change communication: Some implications of an emerging trend. Environmental Communication, 2, 133-153. Searle, J. (1969). Speech acts: An essay in the philosophy of language. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. Space Daily (2007). NASA research suggests Earth climate approaching dangerous point. May 31. Spotts, P. N. (2007). Earth nears tipping point on climate change. Christian Science Monitor, May 30, 2. Walsh, L. (2010). Visual strategies for establishing ethos across the ‘is/ought’ divide in the IPCC’s report Climate Change 2007: Summary for Policy Makers. Poroi, 6, http://dx.doi.org/10.13008/2151-2957.1066 Walton, D. (2003). Relevance in argumentation. London: Routledge. Zarefsky, D. (1990). Lincoln, Douglas, and slavery: In the crucible of public debate. Chicago: University of Chicago Press. Ziman, J. (2000). Are debatable scientific questions debatable? Social Epistemology, 14, 187-199.