SlideShare a Scribd company logo
What is it like to be a bat
http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html
1 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12
What is it like to be a bat?
Thomas Nagel
[From The Philosophical Review LXXXIII, 4 (October 1974):
435-50.]
Consciousness is what makes the mind-body problem really
intractable. Perhaps that is why current
discussions of the problem give it little attention or get it
obviously wrong. The recent wave of
reductionist euphoria has produced several analyses of mental
phenomena and mental concepts designed
to explain the possibility of some variety of materialism,
psychophysical identification, or reduction.
1
But
the problems dealt with are those common to this type of
reduction and other types, and what makes the
mind-body problem unique, and unlike the water-H2O problem
or the Turing machine-IBM machine
problem or the lightning-electrical discharge problem or the
gene-DNA problem or the oak
tree-hydrocarbon problem, is ignored.
Every reductionist has his favorite analogy from modern
science. It is most unlikely that any of these
unrelated examples of successful reduction will shed light on
the relation of mind to brain. But
philosophers share the general human weakness for explanations
of what is incomprehensible in terms
suited for what is familiar and well understood, though entirely
different. This has led to the acceptance of
implausible accounts of the mental largely because they would
permit familiar kinds of reduction. I shall
try to explain why the usual examples do not help us to
understand the relation between mind and
body—why, indeed, we have at present no conception of what
an explanation of the physical nature of a
mental phenomenon would be. Without consciousness the mind-
body problem would be much less
interesting. With consciousness it seems hopeless. The most
important and characteristic feature of
conscious mental phenomena is very poorly understood. Most
reductionist theories do not even try to
explain it. And careful examination will show that no currently
available concept of reduction is
applicable to it. Perhaps a new theoretical form can be devised
for the purpose, but such a solution, if it
exists, lies in the distant intellectual future.
Conscious experience is a widespread phenomenon. It occurs at
many levels of animal life, though we
cannot be sure of its presence in the simpler organisms, and it is
very difficult to say in general what
provides evidence of it. (Some extremists have been prepared to
deny it even of mammals other than
man.) No doubt it occurs in countless forms totally
unimaginable to us, on other planets in other solar
systems throughout the universe. But no matter how the form
may vary, the fact that an organism has
conscious experience at all means, basically, that there is
something it is like to be that organism. There
may be further implications about the form of the experience;
there may even (though I doubt it) be
implications about the behavior of the organism. But
fundamentally an organism has conscious mental
states if and only if there is something that it is to be that
organism—something it is like for the
organism.
We may call this the subjective character of experience. It is not
captured by any of the familiar, recently
devised reductive analyses of the mental, for all of them are
logically compatible with its absence. It is not
analyzable in terms of any explanatory system of functional
states, or intentional states, since these could
What is it like to be a bat
http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html
2 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12
be ascribed to robots or automata that behaved like people
though they experienced nothing.
2
It is not
analyzable in terms of the causal role of experiences in relation
to typical human behavior—for similar
reasons.
3
I do not deny that conscious mental states and events cause
behavior, nor that they may be given
functional characterizations. I deny only that this kind of thing
exhausts their analysis. Any reductionist
program has to be based on an analysis of what is to be reduced.
If the analysis leaves something out, the
problem will be falsely posed. It is useless to base the defense
of materialism on any analysis of mental
phenomena that fails to deal explicitly with their subjective
character. For there is no reason to suppose
that a reduction which seems plausible when no attempt is made
to account for consciousness can be
extended to include consciousness. With out some idea,
therefore, of what the subjective character of
experience is, we cannot know what is required of physicalist
theory.
While an account of the physical basis of mind must explain
many things, this appears to be the most
difficult. It is impossible to exclude the phenomenological
features of experience from a reduction in the
same way that one excludes the phenomenal features of an
ordinary substance from a physical or chemical
reduction of it—namely, by explaining them as effects on the
minds of human observers.
4
If physicalism
is to be defended, the phenomenological features must
themselves be given a physical account. But when
we examine their subjective character it seems that such a result
is impossible. The reason is that every
subjective phenomenon is essentially connected with a single
point of view, and it seems inevitable that
an objective, physical theory will abandon that point of view.
Let me first try to state the issue somewhat more fully than by
referring to the relation between the
subjective and the objective, or between the pour-soi and the
en-soi. This is far from easy. Facts about
what it is like to be an X are very peculiar, so peculiar that
some may be inclined to doubt their reality, or
the significance of claims about them. To illustrate the
connection between subjectivity and a point of
view, and to make evident the importance of subjective features,
it will help to explore the matter in
relation to an example that brings out clearly the divergence
between the two types of conception,
subjective and objective.
I assume we all believe that bats have experience. After all,
they are mammals, and there is no more doubt
that they have experience than that mice or pigeons or whales
have experience. I have chosen bats instead
of wasps or flounders because if one travels too far down the
phylogenetic tree, people gradually shed
their faith that there is experience there at all. Bats, although
more closely related to us than those other
species, nevertheless present a range of activity and a sensory
apparatus so different from ours that the
problem I want to pose is exceptionally vivid (though it
certainly could be raised with other species). Even
without the benefit of philosophical reflection, anyone who has
spent some time in an enclosed space with
an excited bat knows what it is to encounter a fundamentally
alien form of life.
I have said that the essence of the belief that bats have
experience is that there is something that it is like
to be a bat. Now we know that most bats (the microchiroptera,
to be precise) perceive the external world
primarily by sonar, or echolocation, detecting the reflections,
from objects within range, of their own
rapid, subtly modulated, high-frequency shrieks. Their brains
are designed to correlate the outgoing
impulses with the subsequent echoes, and the information thus
acquired enables bats to make precise
discriminations of distance, size, shape, motion, and texture
comparable to those we make by vision. But
bat sonar, though clearly a form of perception, is not similar in
its operation to any sense that we possess,
and there is no reason to suppose that it is subjectively like
anything we can experience or imagine. This
appears to create difficulties for the notion of what it is like to
be a bat. We must consider whether any
method will permit us to extrapolate to the inner life of the bat
from our own case,
5
and if not, what
alternative methods there may be for understanding the notion.
Our own experience provides the basic material for our
imagination, whose range is therefore limited. It
will not help to try to imagine that one has webbing on one's
arms, which enables one to fly around at
dusk and dawn catching insects in one's mouth; that one has
very poor vision, and perceives the
surrounding world by a system of reflected high-frequency
sound signals; and that one spends the day
What is it like to be a bat
http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html
3 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12
hanging upside down by one's feet in an attic. In so far as I can
imagine this (which is not very far), it tells
me only what it would be like for me to behave as a bat
behaves. But that is not the question. I want to
know what it is like for a bat to be a bat. Yet if I try to imagine
this, I am restricted to the resources of my
own mind, and those resources are inadequate to the task. I
cannot perform it either by imagining
additions to my present experience, or by imagining segments
gradually subtracted from it, or by
imagining some combination of additions, subtractions, and
modifications.
To the extent that I could look and behave like a wasp or a bat
without changing my fundamental
structure, my experiences would not be anything like the
experiences of those animals. On the other hand,
it is doubtful that any meaning can be attached to the
supposition that I should possess the internal
neurophysiological constitution of a bat. Even if I could by
gradual degrees be transformed into a bat,
nothing in my present constitution enables me to imagine what
the experiences of such a future stage of
myself thus metamorphosed would be like. The best evidence
would come from the experiences of bats, if
we only knew what they were like.
So if extrapolation from our own case is involved in the idea of
what it is like to be a bat, the
extrapolation must be incompletable. We cannot form more than
a schematic conception of what it is like.
For example, we may ascribe general types of experience on the
basis of the animal's structure and
behavior. Thus we describe bat sonar as a form of three-
dimensional forward perception; we believe that
bats feel some versions of pain, fear, hunger, and lust, and that
they have other, more familiar types of
perception besides sonar. But we believe that these experiences
also have in each case a specific
subjective character, which it is beyond our ability to conceive.
And if there's conscious life elsewhere in
the universe, it is likely that some of it will not be describable
even in the most general experiential terms
available to us.
6
(The problem is not confined to exotic cases, however, for it
exists between one person
and another. The subjective character of the experience of a
person deaf and blind from birth is not
accessible to me, for example, nor presumably is mine to him.
This does not prevent us each from
believing that the other's experience has such a subjective
character.)
If anyone is inclined to deny that we can believe in the
existence of facts like this whose exact nature we
cannot possibly conceive, he should reflect that in
contemplating the bats we are in much the same
position that intelligent bats or Martians
7
would occupy if they tried to form a conception of what it was
like to be us. The structure of their own minds might make it
impossible for them to succeed, but we
know they would be wrong to conclude that there is not
anything precise that it is like to be us: that only
certain general types of mental state could be ascribed to us
(perhaps perception and appetite would be
concepts common to us both; perhaps not). We know they would
be wrong to draw such a skeptical
conclusion because we know what it is like to be us. And we
know that while it includes an enormous
amount of variation and complexity, and while we do not
possess the vocabulary to describe it adequately,
its subjective character is highly specific, and in some respects
describable in terms that can be understood
only by creatures like us. The fact that we cannot expect ever to
accommodate in our language a detailed
description of Martian or bat phenomenology should not lead us
to dismiss as meaningless the claim that
bats and Martians have experiences fully comparable in richness
of detail to our own. It would be fine if
someone were to develop concepts and a theory that enabled us
to think about those things; but such an
understanding may be permanently denied to us by the limits of
our nature. And to deny the reality or
logical significance of what we can never describe or
understand is the crudest form of cognitive
dissonance.
This brings us to the edge of a topic that requires much more
discussion than I can give it here: namely,
the relation between facts on the one hand and conceptual
schemes or systems of representation on the
other. My realism about the subjective domain in all its forms
implies a belief in the existence of facts
beyond the reach of human concepts. Certainly it is possible for
a human being to believe that there are
facts which humans never will possess the requisite concepts to
represent or comprehend. Indeed, it would
be foolish to doubt this, given the finiteness of humanity's
expectations. After all there would have been
transfinite numbers even if everyone had been wiped out by the
Black Death before Cantor discovered
them. But one might also believe that there are facts which
could not ever be represented or
What is it like to be a bat
http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html
4 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12
comprehended by human beings, even if the species lasted for
ever—simply because our structure does
not permit us to operate with concepts of the requisite type.
This impossibility might even be observed by
other beings, but it is not clear that the existence of such
beings, or the possibility of their existence, is a
precondition of the significance of the hypothesis that there are
humanly inaccessible facts. (After all, the
nature of beings with access to humanly inaccessible facts is
presumably itself a humanly inaccessible
fact.) Reflection on what it is like to be a bat seems to lead us,
therefore, to the conclusion that there are
facts that do not consist in the truth of propositions expressible
in a human language. We can be
compelled to recognize the existence of such facts without
being able to state or comprehend them.
I shall not pursue this subject, however. Its bearing on the topic
before us (namely, the mind-body
problem) is that it enables us to make a general observation
about the subjective character of experience.
Whatever may be the status of facts about what it is like to be a
human being, or a bat, or a Martian, these
appear to be facts that embody a particular point of view.
I am not adverting here to the alleged privacy of experience to
its possessor. The point of view in question
is not one accessible only to a single individual. Rather it is a
type. It is often possible to take up a point of
view other than one's own, so the comprehension of such facts
is not limited to one's own case. There is a
sense in which phenomenological facts are perfectly objective:
one person can know or say of another
what the quality of the other's experience is. They are
subjective, however, in the sense that even this
objective ascription of experience is possible only for someone
sufficiently similar to the object of
ascription to be able to adopt his point of view—to understand
the ascription in the first person as well as
in the third, so to speak. The more different from oneself the
other experiencer is, the less success one can
expect with this enterprise. In our own case we occupy the
relevant point of view, but we will have as
much difficulty understanding our own experience properly if
we approach it from another point of view
as we would if we tried to understand the experience of another
species without taking up its point of
view.
8
This bears directly on the mind-body problem. For if the facts
of experience—facts about what it is like
for the experiencing organism—are accessible only from one
point of view, then it is a mystery how the
true character of experiences could be revealed in the physical
operation of that organism. The latter is a
domain of objective facts par excellence—the kind that can be
observed and understood from many points
of view and by individuals with differing perceptual systems.
There are no comparable imaginative
obstacles to the acquisition of knowledge about bat
neurophysiology by human scientists, and intelligent
bats or Martians might learn more about the human brain than
we ever will.
This is not by itself an argument against reduction. A Martian
scientist with no understanding of visual
perception could understand the rainbow, or lightning, or clouds
as physical phenomena, though he would
never be able to understand the human concepts of rainbow,
lightning, or cloud, or the place these things
occupy in our phenomenal world. The objective nature of the
things picked out by these concepts could be
apprehended by him because, although the concepts themselves
are connected with a particular point of
view and a particular visual phenomenology, the things
apprehended from that point of view are not: they
are observable-from the point of view but external to it; hence
they can be comprehended from other
points of view also, either by the same organisms or by others.
Lightning has an objective character that is
not exhausted by its visual appearance, and this can be
investigated by a Martian without vision. To be
precise, it has a more objective character than is revealed in its
visual appearance. In speaking of the move
from subjective to objective characterization, I wish to remain
noncommittal about the existence of an end
point, the completely objective intrinsic nature of the thing,
which one might or might not be able to
reach. It may be more accurate to think of objectivity as a
direction in which the understanding can travel.
And in understanding a phenomenon like lightning, it is
legitimate to go as far away as one can from a
strictly human viewpoint.
9
In the case of experience, on the other hand, the connection
with a particular point of view seems much
closer. It is difficult to understand what could be meant by the
objective character of an experience, apart
from the particular point of view from which its subject
apprehends it. After all, what would be left of
What is it like to be a bat
http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html
5 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12
what it was like to be a bat if one removed the viewpoint of the
bat? But if experience does not have, in
addition to its subjective character, an objective nature that can
be apprehended from many different
points of view, then how can it be supposed that a Martian
investigating my brain might be observing
physical processes which were my mental processes (as he
might observe physical processes which were
bolts of lightning), only from a different point of view? How,
for that matter, could a human physiologist
observe them from another point of view?
10
We appear to be faced with a general difficulty about
psychophysical reduction. In other areas the process
of reduction is a move in the direction of greater objectivity,
toward a more, accurate view of the real
nature of things. This is accomplished by reducing our
dependence on individual or species-specific points
of view toward the object of investigation. We describe it not in
terms of the impressions it makes on our
senses, but in terms of its more general effects and of properties
detectable by means other than the human
senses. The less it depends on a specifically human viewpoint,
the more objective is our description. It is
possible to follow this path because although the concepts and
ideas we employ in thinking about the
external world are initially applied from a point of view that
involves our perceptual apparatus, they are
used by us to refer to things beyond themselves—toward which
we have the phenomenal point of view.
Therefore we can abandon it in favor of another, and still be
thinking about the same things.
Experience itself however, does not seem to fit the pattern. The
idea of moving from appearance to reality
seems to make no sense here. What is the analogue in this case
to pursuing a more objective
understanding of the same phenomena by abandoning the initial
subjective viewpoint toward them in
favour of another that is more objective but concerns the same
thing? Certainly it appears unlikely that we
will get closer to the real nature of human experience by leaving
behind the particularity of our human
point of view and striving for a description in terms accessible
to beings that could not imagine what it
was like to be us. If the subjective character of experience is
fully comprehensible only from one point of
view, then any shift to greater objectivity—that is, less
attachment to a specific viewpoint—does not take
us nearer to the real nature of the phenomenon: it takes us
farther away from it.
In a sense, the seeds of this objection to the reducibility of
experience are already detectable in successful
cases of reduction; for in discovering sound to be, in reality, a
wave phenomenon in air or other media, we
leave behind one viewpoint to take up another, and the auditory,
human or animal viewpoint that we leave
behind remains unreduced. Members of radically different
species may both understand the same physical
events in objective terms, and this does not require that they
understand the phenomenal forms in which
those events appear to the senses of members of the other
species. Thus it is a condition of their referring
to a common reality that their more particular viewpoints are
not part of the common reality that they both
apprehend. The reduction can succeed only if the species-
specific viewpoint is omitted from what is to be
reduced.
But while we are right to leave this point of view aside in
seeking a fuller understanding of the external
world, we cannot ignore it permanently, since it is the essence
of the internal world, and not merely a
point of view on it. Most of the neobehaviorism of recent
philosophical psychology results from the effort
to substitute an objective concept of mind for the real thing, in
order to have nothing left over which
cannot be reduced. If we acknowledge that a physical theory of
mind must account for the subjective
character of experience, we must admit that no presently
available conception gives us a clue how this
could be done. The problem is unique. If mental processes are
indeed physical processes, then there is
something it is like, intrinsically,
11
to undergo certain physical processes. What it is for such a
thing to be
the case remains a mystery.
What moral should be drawn from these reflections, and what
should be done next? It would be a mistake
to conclude that physicalism must be false. Nothing is proved
by the inadequacy of physicalist hypotheses
that assume a faulty objective analysis of mind. It would be
truer to say that physicalism is a position we
cannot understand because we do not at present have any
conception of how it might be true. Perhaps it
will be thought unreasonable to require such a conception as a
condition of understanding. After all, it
might be said, the meaning of physicalism is clear enough:
mental states are states of the body; mental
What is it like to be a bat
http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html
6 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12
events are physical events. We do not know which physical
states and events they are, but that should not
prevent us from understanding the hypothesis. What could be
clearer than the words 'is' and 'are'?
But I believe it is precisely this apparent clarity of the word 'is'
that is deceptive. Usually, when we are
told that X is Y we know how it is supposed to be true, but that
depends on a conceptual or theoretical
background and is not conveyed by the 'is' alone. We know how
both "X" and "Y " refer, and the kinds of
things to which they refer, and we have a rough idea how the
two referential paths might converge on a
single thing, be it an object, a person, a process, an event or
whatever. But when the two terms of the
identification are very disparate it may not be so clear how it
could be true. We may not have even a rough
idea of how the two referential paths could converge, or what
kind of things they might converge on, and
a theoretical framework may have to be supplied to enable us to
understand this. Without the framework,
an air of mysticism surrounds the identification.
This explains the magical flavor of popular presentations of
fundamental scientific discoveries, given out
as propositions to which one must subscribe without really
understanding them. For example, people are
now told at an early age that all matter is really energy. But
despite the fact that -'they know what 'is'
means, most of them never form a conception of what makes
this claim true, because they lack the
theoretical background.
At the present time the status of physicalism is similar to that
which the hypothesis that matter is energy
would have had if uttered by a pre-Socratic philosopher. We do
not have the beginnings of a conception of
how it might be true. In order to understand the hypothesis that
a mental event is a physical event, we
require more than an understanding of the word 'is'. The idea of
how a mental and a physical term might
refer to the same thing is lacking, and the usual analogies with
theoretical identification in other fields fail
to supply it. They fail because if we construe the reference of
mental terms to physical events on the usual
model, we either get a reappearance of separate subjective
events as the effects through which mental
reference to physical events is secured, or else we get a false
account of how mental terms refer (for
example, a causal behaviorist one).
Strangely enough, we may have evidence for the truth of
something we cannot really understand. Suppose
a caterpillar is locked in a sterile safe by someone unfamiliar
with insect metamorphosis, and weeks later
the safe is reopened, revealing a butterfly. If the person knows
that the safe has been shut the whole time,
he has reason to believe that the butterfly is or was once the
caterpillar, without having any idea in what
sense this might be so. (One possibility is that the caterpillar
contained a tiny winged parasite that
devoured it and grew into the butterfly.)
It is conceivable that we are in such a position with regard to
physicalism. Donald Davidson has argued
that if mental events have physical causes and effects, they must
have physical descriptions. He holds that
we have reason to believe this even though we do not—and in
fact could not—have a general
psychophysical theory.
12
His argument applies to intentional mental events, but I think
we also have some
reason to believe that sensations are physical processes, without
being in a position to understand how.
Davidson's position is that certain physical events have
irreducibly mental properties, and perhaps some
view describable in this way is correct. But nothing of which we
can now form a conception corresponds
to it; nor have we any idea what a theory would be like that
enabled us to conceive of it.
13
Very little work has been done on the basic question (from
which mention of the brain can be entirely
omitted) whether any sense can be made of experiences' having
an objective character at all. Does it make
sense, in other words, to ask what my experiences are really
like, as opposed to how they appear to me?
We cannot genuinely understand the hypothesis that their nature
is captured in a physical description
unless we understand the more fundamental idea that they have
an objective nature (or that objective
processes can have a subjective nature).
14
I should like to close with a speculative proposal. It may be
possible to approach the gap between
subjective and objective from another direction. Setting aside
temporarily the relation between the mind
What is it like to be a bat
http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html
7 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12
and the brain, we can pursue a more objective understanding of
the mental in its own right. At present we
are completely unequipped to think about the subjective
character of experience without relying on the
imagination—without taking up the point of view of the
experiential subject. This should be regarded as a
challenge to form new concepts and devise a new method—an
objective phenomenology not dependent
on empathy or the imagination. Though presumably it would not
capture everything, its goal would be to
describe, at least in part, the subjective character of experiences
in a form comprehensible to beings
incapable of having those experiences.
We would have to develop such a phenomenology to describe
the sonar experiences of bats; but it would
also be possible to begin with humans. One might try, for
example, to develop concepts that could be used
to explain to a person blind from birth what it was like to see.
One would reach a blank wall eventually,
but it should be possible to devise a method of expressing in
objective terms much more than we can at
present, and with much greater precision. The loose intermodal
analogies—for example, 'Red is like the
sound of a trumpet'—which crop up in discussions of this
subject are of little use. That should be clear to
anyone who has both heard a trumpet and seen red. But
structural features of perception might be more
accessible to objective description, even though something
would be left out. And concepts alternative to
those we learn in the first person may enable us to arrive at a
kind of understanding even of our own
experience which is denied us by the very ease of description
and lack of distance that subjective concepts
afford.
Apart from its own interest, a phenomenology that is in this
sense objective may permit questions about
the physically basis of experience to assume a more intelligible
form. Aspects of subjective experience
that admitted this kind of objective description might be better
candidates for objective explanations of a
more familiar sort. But whether or not this guess is correct, it
seems unlikely that any physical theory of
mind can be contemplated until more thought has been given to
the general problem of subjective and
objective. Otherwise we cannot even pose the mind-body
problem without sidestepping it.
NOTES:
1
Examples are J. J. C. Smart, Philosophy and Scientific Realism
(London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1963); David K.
Lewis, 'An Argument for the Identity Theory', Journal of
Philosophy, LXIII (1966), reprinted with addenda in David
M. Rosenthal, Materialism & the Mind-Body Problem,
(Engelwood Cliffs, NJ.: Prentice-Hall, 1971); Hilary Putnam,
'Psychological Predicates', in Art, Mind, & Religion, ed. W. H.
Capitan and D. D. Merrill (Pittsburgh: University of
Pittsburgh Press, 1967), reprinted in Materialism, ed. Rosenthal,
as 'The Nature of Mental States'; D. M. Armstrong, A
Materialist Theory of the Mind (London: Routledge & Kegan
Paul, 1968); D. C. Dennett, Content and Consciousness
(London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1969). I have expressed
earlier doubts in 'Armstrong on the Mind', Philosophical
Review, LXXIX (1970), 394-403; a review of Dennett, Journal
of Philosophy, LXIX (1972); and chapter 11 above.
See also Saul Kripke, 'Naming and Necessity'. in Semantics of
Natural Language, ed. D. Davidson and G. Harman
(Dordrecht: Reidel, 1972), esp. pp. 334-42; and M. T. Thornton,
'Ostensive Terms and Materialism', The Monist, LVI
(1972), 193-214.
2
Perhaps there could not actually be such robots. Perhaps
anything complex enough to behave like a person would
have experiences. But that, if true, is a fact which cannot be
discovered merely by analyzing the concept of experience.
3
It is not equivalent to that about which we are incorrigible,
both because we are not incorrigible about experience
and because experience is present in animals lacking language
and thought, who have no beliefs at all about their
experiences.
4
Cf. Richard Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and
Categories', Review of Metaphysics, XIX (1965), esp. 37-8.
5
By 'our own case' I do not mean just 'my own case', but rather
the mentalistic ideas that we apply unproblematically
to ourselves and other human beings.
6
Therefore the analogical form of the English expression 'what it
is like' is misleading. It does not mean 'what (in our
experience) it resembles', but rather 'how it is for the subject
himself'.
What is it like to be a bat
http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html
8 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12
7
Any intelligent extraterrestrial beings totally different from us.
8
It may be easier than I suppose to transcend inter-species
barriers with the aid of the imagination. For example, blind
people are able to detect objects near them by a form of sonar,
using vocal clicks or taps of a cane. Perhaps if one
knew what that was like, one could by extension imagine
roughly what it was like to possess the much more refined
sonar of a bat. The distance between oneself and other persons
and other species can fall anywhere on a continuum.
Even for other persons the understanding of what it is like to be
them is only partial, and when one moves to species
very different from oneself, a lesser degree of partial
understanding may still be available. The imagination is
remarkably flexible. My point, however, is not that we cannot
know what it is like to be a bat. I am not raising that
epistemological problem. My point is rather that even to form a
conception of what it is like to be a bat (and a fortiori
to know what it is like to be a bat) one must take up the bat's
point of view. If one can take it up roughly, or partially,
then one's conception will also be rough or partial. Or so it
seems in our present state of understanding.
9
The problem I am going to raise can therefore be posed even if
the distinction between more subjective and more
objective descriptions or viewpoints can itself be made only
within a larger human point of view. I do not accept this
kind of conceptual relativism, but it need not be refuted to make
the point that psychophysical reduction cannot be
accommodated by the subjective-to-objective model from other
cases.
10
The problem is not just that when I look at the Mona Lisa, my
visual experience has a certain quality, no trace of
which is to be found by someone looking into my brain. For
even if he did observe there a tiny image of the Mona
Lisa, he would have no reason to identify it with the experience.
11
The relation would therefore not be a contingent one, like that
of a cause and its distinct effect. It would be
necessarily true that a physical state felt a certain way. Saul
Kripke in Semantics of Natural Language, (ed. Davidson
and Harman) argues that causal behaviorist and related analyses
of the mental fail because they construe, e.g., 'pain' as
a merely contingent name of pains. The subjective character of
an experience ('its immediate phenomenolocal quality'
Kripke calls it (p. 340)) is the essential property left out by
such analyses, and the one in virtue of which it is,
necessarily, the experience it is. My view is closely related to
his. Like Kripke, I find the hypothesis that a certain
brain state should necessarily have a certain subjective
character incomprehensible without further explanation. No
such explanation emerges from theories which view the mind-
brain relation as contingent, but perhaps there are other
alternatives, not yet discovered.
A theory that explained how the mind-brain relation was
necessary would still leave us with Kripke's problem of
explaining why it nevertheless appears contingent. That
difficulty seems to me surmountable, in the following way.
We may imagine something by representing it to ourselves
either perceptually, sympathetically, or symbolically. I shall
not try to say how symbolic imagination works, but part of what
happens in the other two cases is this. To imagine
something perceptually, we put ourselves in a conscious state
resembling the state we would be in if we perceived it.
To imagine something sympathetically, we put ourselves in a
conscious state resembling the thing itself. (This method
can be used only to imagine mental events and stares—our own
or another's.) When we try to imagine a mental state
occurring without its associated brain state, we first
sympathetically imagine the occurrence of the mental state: that
is,
we put ourselves into a state that resembles it mentally. At the
same time, we attempt perceptually to imagine the
nonoccurrence of the associated physical state, by putting
ourselves into another state unconnected with the first; one
resembling that which we would be in if we perceived the
nonoccurrence of the physical state. Where the imagination
of physical features is perceptual and the imagination of mental
features is sympathetic, it appears to us that we can
imagine any experience occurring without its associated brain
state, and vice versa. The relation between them will
appear contingent even if it is necessary, because of the
independence of the disparate types of imagination.
(Solipsism incidentally, results if one misinterprets sympathetic
imagination as if it worked like perceptual
imagination: it then seems impossible to imagine any experience
that is not one's own.)
12
See 'Mental Events' in Experience and Theory, ed. Lawrence
Foster and J. W. Swanson (Amherst: University of
Massachusetts Press, 1970); though I do not understand the
argument against psychophysical laws.
13
Similar remarks apply to my paper 'Physicalism', Philosophical
Review, LXXIV (1965), 339-56, reprinted with
postscript in Modern Materialism, ed. John O'Connor (New
York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1969).
14
This question also lies at the heart of the problem of other
minds, whose close connection with the mind-body
problem is often overlooked. If one understood how subjective
experience could have an objective nature, one would
What is it like to be a bat
http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html
9 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12
understand the existence of subjects other than oneself.
15
I have not defined the term 'physical'. Obviously it does not
apply just to what can be described by the concepts of
contemporary physics, since we expect further developments.
Some may think there is nothing to prevent mental
phenomena from eventually being recognized as physical in
their own right. But whatever else may be said of the
physical, it has to be objective. So if our idea of the physical
ever expands to include mental phenomena, it will have
to assign them an objective character—whether or not this is
done by analyzing them in terms of other phenomena
already regarded as physical It seems to me more likely,
however, that mental-physical relations will eventually be
expressed in a theory whose fundamental terms cannot be
placed clearly in either category.

More Related Content

DOCX
BRAINS, MINDS, AND CONSCIOuSNESSNo area of the debate betwee.docx
DOCX
Psychology as the behaviorist views it
PDF
Perplexities Of Consciousness Schwitzgebel Ericauthor
ODT
Why "Eternal Life" May be a Valid Scientific Concept - No Religion or White F...
DOCX
Gilbert Ryle. 1949. Descartes’ Myth”, Chapter 1 of The Concep.docx
PDF
Theory Of Knowledge
PDF
The problem with the metamprphisis of plants
PPT
The Emergence of Consciousness at Lighthouse
BRAINS, MINDS, AND CONSCIOuSNESSNo area of the debate betwee.docx
Psychology as the behaviorist views it
Perplexities Of Consciousness Schwitzgebel Ericauthor
Why "Eternal Life" May be a Valid Scientific Concept - No Religion or White F...
Gilbert Ryle. 1949. Descartes’ Myth”, Chapter 1 of The Concep.docx
Theory Of Knowledge
The problem with the metamprphisis of plants
The Emergence of Consciousness at Lighthouse

Similar to What is it like to be a bat httpmembers.aol.comNeoNoetics.docx (13)

PDF
Are electrons conscious?By.Dr.Mahboob ali khan Phd
PDF
Play All Night Duane Allman And The Journey To Fillmore East Bob Beatty
DOCX
Why Nagel Is Right
DOCX
Double_Slit_Experiment_Biocentrism
DOCX
Sistema kinslow
PDF
Reflexive monism final_version_december_2007
PDF
Consciousness as a Limitation
PDF
Course 0837 assingment 1 roll no ce529580
PPT
Nagel, bats, and the hard problem
PDF
Advances In Chemical Physics Vol118 1st Edition I Prigogine
PDF
10 Amazing Pirates 1st Edition Jack Goldstein
PDF
Psychology Capstone Project Examples
Are electrons conscious?By.Dr.Mahboob ali khan Phd
Play All Night Duane Allman And The Journey To Fillmore East Bob Beatty
Why Nagel Is Right
Double_Slit_Experiment_Biocentrism
Sistema kinslow
Reflexive monism final_version_december_2007
Consciousness as a Limitation
Course 0837 assingment 1 roll no ce529580
Nagel, bats, and the hard problem
Advances In Chemical Physics Vol118 1st Edition I Prigogine
10 Amazing Pirates 1st Edition Jack Goldstein
Psychology Capstone Project Examples
Ad

More from helzerpatrina (20)

DOCX
Most patients with mental health disorders are not aggressive. H.docx
DOCX
MotivationExplain your motivation for applying to this prog.docx
DOCX
Most public policy is made from within government agencies. Select a.docx
DOCX
Mr. Smith brings his 4-year-old son to your primary care office. He .docx
DOCX
Mrs. Walsh, a woman in her 70s, was in critical condition after rep.docx
DOCX
Much has been made of the new Web 2.0 phenomenon, including social n.docx
DOCX
MSN 5550 Health Promotion Prevention of Disease Case Study Module 2.docx
DOCX
MSEL Strategy Mid-term Instructions Miguel Rivera-SantosFormat.docx
DOCX
Much of the focus in network security centers upon measures in preve.docx
DOCX
Mt. Baker Hazards Hazard Rating Score High silic.docx
DOCX
Motivation and Cognitive FactorsQuestion AAlfred Hit.docx
DOCX
Motivation in OrganizationsMotivation i.docx
DOCX
Motivations to Support Charity-Linked Events After Exposure to.docx
DOCX
Mrs. Walsh, a woman in her 70s, was in critical condition after.docx
DOCX
MOVIE TITLE IS LIAR LIAR starring JIM CARREYProvide the name o.docx
DOCX
mple selection, and assignment to groups (as applicable). Describe.docx
DOCX
More and more businesses have integrated social media into every asp.docx
DOCX
Module Five Directions for the ComparisonContrast EssayWrite a.docx
DOCX
Monica asked that we meet to see if I could help to reduce the d.docx
DOCX
Module 6 AssignmentPlease list and describe four types of Cy.docx
Most patients with mental health disorders are not aggressive. H.docx
MotivationExplain your motivation for applying to this prog.docx
Most public policy is made from within government agencies. Select a.docx
Mr. Smith brings his 4-year-old son to your primary care office. He .docx
Mrs. Walsh, a woman in her 70s, was in critical condition after rep.docx
Much has been made of the new Web 2.0 phenomenon, including social n.docx
MSN 5550 Health Promotion Prevention of Disease Case Study Module 2.docx
MSEL Strategy Mid-term Instructions Miguel Rivera-SantosFormat.docx
Much of the focus in network security centers upon measures in preve.docx
Mt. Baker Hazards Hazard Rating Score High silic.docx
Motivation and Cognitive FactorsQuestion AAlfred Hit.docx
Motivation in OrganizationsMotivation i.docx
Motivations to Support Charity-Linked Events After Exposure to.docx
Mrs. Walsh, a woman in her 70s, was in critical condition after.docx
MOVIE TITLE IS LIAR LIAR starring JIM CARREYProvide the name o.docx
mple selection, and assignment to groups (as applicable). Describe.docx
More and more businesses have integrated social media into every asp.docx
Module Five Directions for the ComparisonContrast EssayWrite a.docx
Monica asked that we meet to see if I could help to reduce the d.docx
Module 6 AssignmentPlease list and describe four types of Cy.docx
Ad

Recently uploaded (20)

PPTX
Introduction to Building Materials
PPTX
A powerpoint presentation on the Revised K-10 Science Shaping Paper
PDF
ChatGPT for Dummies - Pam Baker Ccesa007.pdf
PPTX
Final Presentation General Medicine 03-08-2024.pptx
PDF
Classroom Observation Tools for Teachers
PDF
Trump Administration's workforce development strategy
PDF
medical_surgical_nursing_10th_edition_ignatavicius_TEST_BANK_pdf.pdf
PPTX
Chinmaya Tiranga Azadi Quiz (Class 7-8 )
PDF
Supply Chain Operations Speaking Notes -ICLT Program
PPTX
History, Philosophy and sociology of education (1).pptx
PDF
Empowerment Technology for Senior High School Guide
PDF
Indian roads congress 037 - 2012 Flexible pavement
PDF
1_English_Language_Set_2.pdf probationary
PDF
GENETICS IN BIOLOGY IN SECONDARY LEVEL FORM 3
PPTX
1st Inaugural Professorial Lecture held on 19th February 2020 (Governance and...
PPTX
Lesson notes of climatology university.
PDF
Hazard Identification & Risk Assessment .pdf
PPTX
UV-Visible spectroscopy..pptx UV-Visible Spectroscopy – Electronic Transition...
PDF
احياء السادس العلمي - الفصل الثالث (التكاثر) منهج متميزين/كلية بغداد/موهوبين
PDF
What if we spent less time fighting change, and more time building what’s rig...
Introduction to Building Materials
A powerpoint presentation on the Revised K-10 Science Shaping Paper
ChatGPT for Dummies - Pam Baker Ccesa007.pdf
Final Presentation General Medicine 03-08-2024.pptx
Classroom Observation Tools for Teachers
Trump Administration's workforce development strategy
medical_surgical_nursing_10th_edition_ignatavicius_TEST_BANK_pdf.pdf
Chinmaya Tiranga Azadi Quiz (Class 7-8 )
Supply Chain Operations Speaking Notes -ICLT Program
History, Philosophy and sociology of education (1).pptx
Empowerment Technology for Senior High School Guide
Indian roads congress 037 - 2012 Flexible pavement
1_English_Language_Set_2.pdf probationary
GENETICS IN BIOLOGY IN SECONDARY LEVEL FORM 3
1st Inaugural Professorial Lecture held on 19th February 2020 (Governance and...
Lesson notes of climatology university.
Hazard Identification & Risk Assessment .pdf
UV-Visible spectroscopy..pptx UV-Visible Spectroscopy – Electronic Transition...
احياء السادس العلمي - الفصل الثالث (التكاثر) منهج متميزين/كلية بغداد/موهوبين
What if we spent less time fighting change, and more time building what’s rig...

What is it like to be a bat httpmembers.aol.comNeoNoetics.docx

  • 1. What is it like to be a bat http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html 1 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12 What is it like to be a bat? Thomas Nagel [From The Philosophical Review LXXXIII, 4 (October 1974): 435-50.] Consciousness is what makes the mind-body problem really intractable. Perhaps that is why current discussions of the problem give it little attention or get it obviously wrong. The recent wave of reductionist euphoria has produced several analyses of mental phenomena and mental concepts designed to explain the possibility of some variety of materialism, psychophysical identification, or reduction. 1 But the problems dealt with are those common to this type of reduction and other types, and what makes the mind-body problem unique, and unlike the water-H2O problem or the Turing machine-IBM machine
  • 2. problem or the lightning-electrical discharge problem or the gene-DNA problem or the oak tree-hydrocarbon problem, is ignored. Every reductionist has his favorite analogy from modern science. It is most unlikely that any of these unrelated examples of successful reduction will shed light on the relation of mind to brain. But philosophers share the general human weakness for explanations of what is incomprehensible in terms suited for what is familiar and well understood, though entirely different. This has led to the acceptance of implausible accounts of the mental largely because they would permit familiar kinds of reduction. I shall try to explain why the usual examples do not help us to understand the relation between mind and body—why, indeed, we have at present no conception of what an explanation of the physical nature of a mental phenomenon would be. Without consciousness the mind- body problem would be much less interesting. With consciousness it seems hopeless. The most important and characteristic feature of conscious mental phenomena is very poorly understood. Most reductionist theories do not even try to
  • 3. explain it. And careful examination will show that no currently available concept of reduction is applicable to it. Perhaps a new theoretical form can be devised for the purpose, but such a solution, if it exists, lies in the distant intellectual future. Conscious experience is a widespread phenomenon. It occurs at many levels of animal life, though we cannot be sure of its presence in the simpler organisms, and it is very difficult to say in general what provides evidence of it. (Some extremists have been prepared to deny it even of mammals other than man.) No doubt it occurs in countless forms totally unimaginable to us, on other planets in other solar systems throughout the universe. But no matter how the form may vary, the fact that an organism has conscious experience at all means, basically, that there is something it is like to be that organism. There may be further implications about the form of the experience; there may even (though I doubt it) be implications about the behavior of the organism. But fundamentally an organism has conscious mental states if and only if there is something that it is to be that organism—something it is like for the organism.
  • 4. We may call this the subjective character of experience. It is not captured by any of the familiar, recently devised reductive analyses of the mental, for all of them are logically compatible with its absence. It is not analyzable in terms of any explanatory system of functional states, or intentional states, since these could What is it like to be a bat http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html 2 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12 be ascribed to robots or automata that behaved like people though they experienced nothing. 2 It is not analyzable in terms of the causal role of experiences in relation to typical human behavior—for similar reasons. 3 I do not deny that conscious mental states and events cause behavior, nor that they may be given functional characterizations. I deny only that this kind of thing exhausts their analysis. Any reductionist program has to be based on an analysis of what is to be reduced. If the analysis leaves something out, the
  • 5. problem will be falsely posed. It is useless to base the defense of materialism on any analysis of mental phenomena that fails to deal explicitly with their subjective character. For there is no reason to suppose that a reduction which seems plausible when no attempt is made to account for consciousness can be extended to include consciousness. With out some idea, therefore, of what the subjective character of experience is, we cannot know what is required of physicalist theory. While an account of the physical basis of mind must explain many things, this appears to be the most difficult. It is impossible to exclude the phenomenological features of experience from a reduction in the same way that one excludes the phenomenal features of an ordinary substance from a physical or chemical reduction of it—namely, by explaining them as effects on the minds of human observers. 4 If physicalism is to be defended, the phenomenological features must themselves be given a physical account. But when we examine their subjective character it seems that such a result is impossible. The reason is that every subjective phenomenon is essentially connected with a single
  • 6. point of view, and it seems inevitable that an objective, physical theory will abandon that point of view. Let me first try to state the issue somewhat more fully than by referring to the relation between the subjective and the objective, or between the pour-soi and the en-soi. This is far from easy. Facts about what it is like to be an X are very peculiar, so peculiar that some may be inclined to doubt their reality, or the significance of claims about them. To illustrate the connection between subjectivity and a point of view, and to make evident the importance of subjective features, it will help to explore the matter in relation to an example that brings out clearly the divergence between the two types of conception, subjective and objective. I assume we all believe that bats have experience. After all, they are mammals, and there is no more doubt that they have experience than that mice or pigeons or whales have experience. I have chosen bats instead of wasps or flounders because if one travels too far down the phylogenetic tree, people gradually shed their faith that there is experience there at all. Bats, although more closely related to us than those other
  • 7. species, nevertheless present a range of activity and a sensory apparatus so different from ours that the problem I want to pose is exceptionally vivid (though it certainly could be raised with other species). Even without the benefit of philosophical reflection, anyone who has spent some time in an enclosed space with an excited bat knows what it is to encounter a fundamentally alien form of life. I have said that the essence of the belief that bats have experience is that there is something that it is like to be a bat. Now we know that most bats (the microchiroptera, to be precise) perceive the external world primarily by sonar, or echolocation, detecting the reflections, from objects within range, of their own rapid, subtly modulated, high-frequency shrieks. Their brains are designed to correlate the outgoing impulses with the subsequent echoes, and the information thus acquired enables bats to make precise discriminations of distance, size, shape, motion, and texture comparable to those we make by vision. But bat sonar, though clearly a form of perception, is not similar in its operation to any sense that we possess, and there is no reason to suppose that it is subjectively like anything we can experience or imagine. This
  • 8. appears to create difficulties for the notion of what it is like to be a bat. We must consider whether any method will permit us to extrapolate to the inner life of the bat from our own case, 5 and if not, what alternative methods there may be for understanding the notion. Our own experience provides the basic material for our imagination, whose range is therefore limited. It will not help to try to imagine that one has webbing on one's arms, which enables one to fly around at dusk and dawn catching insects in one's mouth; that one has very poor vision, and perceives the surrounding world by a system of reflected high-frequency sound signals; and that one spends the day What is it like to be a bat http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html 3 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12 hanging upside down by one's feet in an attic. In so far as I can imagine this (which is not very far), it tells me only what it would be like for me to behave as a bat behaves. But that is not the question. I want to know what it is like for a bat to be a bat. Yet if I try to imagine
  • 9. this, I am restricted to the resources of my own mind, and those resources are inadequate to the task. I cannot perform it either by imagining additions to my present experience, or by imagining segments gradually subtracted from it, or by imagining some combination of additions, subtractions, and modifications. To the extent that I could look and behave like a wasp or a bat without changing my fundamental structure, my experiences would not be anything like the experiences of those animals. On the other hand, it is doubtful that any meaning can be attached to the supposition that I should possess the internal neurophysiological constitution of a bat. Even if I could by gradual degrees be transformed into a bat, nothing in my present constitution enables me to imagine what the experiences of such a future stage of myself thus metamorphosed would be like. The best evidence would come from the experiences of bats, if we only knew what they were like. So if extrapolation from our own case is involved in the idea of what it is like to be a bat, the extrapolation must be incompletable. We cannot form more than a schematic conception of what it is like.
  • 10. For example, we may ascribe general types of experience on the basis of the animal's structure and behavior. Thus we describe bat sonar as a form of three- dimensional forward perception; we believe that bats feel some versions of pain, fear, hunger, and lust, and that they have other, more familiar types of perception besides sonar. But we believe that these experiences also have in each case a specific subjective character, which it is beyond our ability to conceive. And if there's conscious life elsewhere in the universe, it is likely that some of it will not be describable even in the most general experiential terms available to us. 6 (The problem is not confined to exotic cases, however, for it exists between one person and another. The subjective character of the experience of a person deaf and blind from birth is not accessible to me, for example, nor presumably is mine to him. This does not prevent us each from believing that the other's experience has such a subjective character.) If anyone is inclined to deny that we can believe in the existence of facts like this whose exact nature we
  • 11. cannot possibly conceive, he should reflect that in contemplating the bats we are in much the same position that intelligent bats or Martians 7 would occupy if they tried to form a conception of what it was like to be us. The structure of their own minds might make it impossible for them to succeed, but we know they would be wrong to conclude that there is not anything precise that it is like to be us: that only certain general types of mental state could be ascribed to us (perhaps perception and appetite would be concepts common to us both; perhaps not). We know they would be wrong to draw such a skeptical conclusion because we know what it is like to be us. And we know that while it includes an enormous amount of variation and complexity, and while we do not possess the vocabulary to describe it adequately, its subjective character is highly specific, and in some respects describable in terms that can be understood only by creatures like us. The fact that we cannot expect ever to accommodate in our language a detailed description of Martian or bat phenomenology should not lead us to dismiss as meaningless the claim that bats and Martians have experiences fully comparable in richness of detail to our own. It would be fine if
  • 12. someone were to develop concepts and a theory that enabled us to think about those things; but such an understanding may be permanently denied to us by the limits of our nature. And to deny the reality or logical significance of what we can never describe or understand is the crudest form of cognitive dissonance. This brings us to the edge of a topic that requires much more discussion than I can give it here: namely, the relation between facts on the one hand and conceptual schemes or systems of representation on the other. My realism about the subjective domain in all its forms implies a belief in the existence of facts beyond the reach of human concepts. Certainly it is possible for a human being to believe that there are facts which humans never will possess the requisite concepts to represent or comprehend. Indeed, it would be foolish to doubt this, given the finiteness of humanity's expectations. After all there would have been transfinite numbers even if everyone had been wiped out by the Black Death before Cantor discovered them. But one might also believe that there are facts which could not ever be represented or
  • 13. What is it like to be a bat http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html 4 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12 comprehended by human beings, even if the species lasted for ever—simply because our structure does not permit us to operate with concepts of the requisite type. This impossibility might even be observed by other beings, but it is not clear that the existence of such beings, or the possibility of their existence, is a precondition of the significance of the hypothesis that there are humanly inaccessible facts. (After all, the nature of beings with access to humanly inaccessible facts is presumably itself a humanly inaccessible fact.) Reflection on what it is like to be a bat seems to lead us, therefore, to the conclusion that there are facts that do not consist in the truth of propositions expressible in a human language. We can be compelled to recognize the existence of such facts without being able to state or comprehend them. I shall not pursue this subject, however. Its bearing on the topic before us (namely, the mind-body problem) is that it enables us to make a general observation about the subjective character of experience.
  • 14. Whatever may be the status of facts about what it is like to be a human being, or a bat, or a Martian, these appear to be facts that embody a particular point of view. I am not adverting here to the alleged privacy of experience to its possessor. The point of view in question is not one accessible only to a single individual. Rather it is a type. It is often possible to take up a point of view other than one's own, so the comprehension of such facts is not limited to one's own case. There is a sense in which phenomenological facts are perfectly objective: one person can know or say of another what the quality of the other's experience is. They are subjective, however, in the sense that even this objective ascription of experience is possible only for someone sufficiently similar to the object of ascription to be able to adopt his point of view—to understand the ascription in the first person as well as in the third, so to speak. The more different from oneself the other experiencer is, the less success one can expect with this enterprise. In our own case we occupy the relevant point of view, but we will have as much difficulty understanding our own experience properly if we approach it from another point of view
  • 15. as we would if we tried to understand the experience of another species without taking up its point of view. 8 This bears directly on the mind-body problem. For if the facts of experience—facts about what it is like for the experiencing organism—are accessible only from one point of view, then it is a mystery how the true character of experiences could be revealed in the physical operation of that organism. The latter is a domain of objective facts par excellence—the kind that can be observed and understood from many points of view and by individuals with differing perceptual systems. There are no comparable imaginative obstacles to the acquisition of knowledge about bat neurophysiology by human scientists, and intelligent bats or Martians might learn more about the human brain than we ever will. This is not by itself an argument against reduction. A Martian scientist with no understanding of visual perception could understand the rainbow, or lightning, or clouds as physical phenomena, though he would never be able to understand the human concepts of rainbow, lightning, or cloud, or the place these things
  • 16. occupy in our phenomenal world. The objective nature of the things picked out by these concepts could be apprehended by him because, although the concepts themselves are connected with a particular point of view and a particular visual phenomenology, the things apprehended from that point of view are not: they are observable-from the point of view but external to it; hence they can be comprehended from other points of view also, either by the same organisms or by others. Lightning has an objective character that is not exhausted by its visual appearance, and this can be investigated by a Martian without vision. To be precise, it has a more objective character than is revealed in its visual appearance. In speaking of the move from subjective to objective characterization, I wish to remain noncommittal about the existence of an end point, the completely objective intrinsic nature of the thing, which one might or might not be able to reach. It may be more accurate to think of objectivity as a direction in which the understanding can travel. And in understanding a phenomenon like lightning, it is legitimate to go as far away as one can from a strictly human viewpoint. 9
  • 17. In the case of experience, on the other hand, the connection with a particular point of view seems much closer. It is difficult to understand what could be meant by the objective character of an experience, apart from the particular point of view from which its subject apprehends it. After all, what would be left of What is it like to be a bat http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html 5 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12 what it was like to be a bat if one removed the viewpoint of the bat? But if experience does not have, in addition to its subjective character, an objective nature that can be apprehended from many different points of view, then how can it be supposed that a Martian investigating my brain might be observing physical processes which were my mental processes (as he might observe physical processes which were bolts of lightning), only from a different point of view? How, for that matter, could a human physiologist observe them from another point of view? 10 We appear to be faced with a general difficulty about
  • 18. psychophysical reduction. In other areas the process of reduction is a move in the direction of greater objectivity, toward a more, accurate view of the real nature of things. This is accomplished by reducing our dependence on individual or species-specific points of view toward the object of investigation. We describe it not in terms of the impressions it makes on our senses, but in terms of its more general effects and of properties detectable by means other than the human senses. The less it depends on a specifically human viewpoint, the more objective is our description. It is possible to follow this path because although the concepts and ideas we employ in thinking about the external world are initially applied from a point of view that involves our perceptual apparatus, they are used by us to refer to things beyond themselves—toward which we have the phenomenal point of view. Therefore we can abandon it in favor of another, and still be thinking about the same things. Experience itself however, does not seem to fit the pattern. The idea of moving from appearance to reality seems to make no sense here. What is the analogue in this case to pursuing a more objective understanding of the same phenomena by abandoning the initial
  • 19. subjective viewpoint toward them in favour of another that is more objective but concerns the same thing? Certainly it appears unlikely that we will get closer to the real nature of human experience by leaving behind the particularity of our human point of view and striving for a description in terms accessible to beings that could not imagine what it was like to be us. If the subjective character of experience is fully comprehensible only from one point of view, then any shift to greater objectivity—that is, less attachment to a specific viewpoint—does not take us nearer to the real nature of the phenomenon: it takes us farther away from it. In a sense, the seeds of this objection to the reducibility of experience are already detectable in successful cases of reduction; for in discovering sound to be, in reality, a wave phenomenon in air or other media, we leave behind one viewpoint to take up another, and the auditory, human or animal viewpoint that we leave behind remains unreduced. Members of radically different species may both understand the same physical events in objective terms, and this does not require that they understand the phenomenal forms in which those events appear to the senses of members of the other
  • 20. species. Thus it is a condition of their referring to a common reality that their more particular viewpoints are not part of the common reality that they both apprehend. The reduction can succeed only if the species- specific viewpoint is omitted from what is to be reduced. But while we are right to leave this point of view aside in seeking a fuller understanding of the external world, we cannot ignore it permanently, since it is the essence of the internal world, and not merely a point of view on it. Most of the neobehaviorism of recent philosophical psychology results from the effort to substitute an objective concept of mind for the real thing, in order to have nothing left over which cannot be reduced. If we acknowledge that a physical theory of mind must account for the subjective character of experience, we must admit that no presently available conception gives us a clue how this could be done. The problem is unique. If mental processes are indeed physical processes, then there is something it is like, intrinsically, 11 to undergo certain physical processes. What it is for such a thing to be
  • 21. the case remains a mystery. What moral should be drawn from these reflections, and what should be done next? It would be a mistake to conclude that physicalism must be false. Nothing is proved by the inadequacy of physicalist hypotheses that assume a faulty objective analysis of mind. It would be truer to say that physicalism is a position we cannot understand because we do not at present have any conception of how it might be true. Perhaps it will be thought unreasonable to require such a conception as a condition of understanding. After all, it might be said, the meaning of physicalism is clear enough: mental states are states of the body; mental What is it like to be a bat http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html 6 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12 events are physical events. We do not know which physical states and events they are, but that should not prevent us from understanding the hypothesis. What could be clearer than the words 'is' and 'are'? But I believe it is precisely this apparent clarity of the word 'is' that is deceptive. Usually, when we are
  • 22. told that X is Y we know how it is supposed to be true, but that depends on a conceptual or theoretical background and is not conveyed by the 'is' alone. We know how both "X" and "Y " refer, and the kinds of things to which they refer, and we have a rough idea how the two referential paths might converge on a single thing, be it an object, a person, a process, an event or whatever. But when the two terms of the identification are very disparate it may not be so clear how it could be true. We may not have even a rough idea of how the two referential paths could converge, or what kind of things they might converge on, and a theoretical framework may have to be supplied to enable us to understand this. Without the framework, an air of mysticism surrounds the identification. This explains the magical flavor of popular presentations of fundamental scientific discoveries, given out as propositions to which one must subscribe without really understanding them. For example, people are now told at an early age that all matter is really energy. But despite the fact that -'they know what 'is' means, most of them never form a conception of what makes this claim true, because they lack the
  • 23. theoretical background. At the present time the status of physicalism is similar to that which the hypothesis that matter is energy would have had if uttered by a pre-Socratic philosopher. We do not have the beginnings of a conception of how it might be true. In order to understand the hypothesis that a mental event is a physical event, we require more than an understanding of the word 'is'. The idea of how a mental and a physical term might refer to the same thing is lacking, and the usual analogies with theoretical identification in other fields fail to supply it. They fail because if we construe the reference of mental terms to physical events on the usual model, we either get a reappearance of separate subjective events as the effects through which mental reference to physical events is secured, or else we get a false account of how mental terms refer (for example, a causal behaviorist one). Strangely enough, we may have evidence for the truth of something we cannot really understand. Suppose a caterpillar is locked in a sterile safe by someone unfamiliar with insect metamorphosis, and weeks later the safe is reopened, revealing a butterfly. If the person knows that the safe has been shut the whole time,
  • 24. he has reason to believe that the butterfly is or was once the caterpillar, without having any idea in what sense this might be so. (One possibility is that the caterpillar contained a tiny winged parasite that devoured it and grew into the butterfly.) It is conceivable that we are in such a position with regard to physicalism. Donald Davidson has argued that if mental events have physical causes and effects, they must have physical descriptions. He holds that we have reason to believe this even though we do not—and in fact could not—have a general psychophysical theory. 12 His argument applies to intentional mental events, but I think we also have some reason to believe that sensations are physical processes, without being in a position to understand how. Davidson's position is that certain physical events have irreducibly mental properties, and perhaps some view describable in this way is correct. But nothing of which we can now form a conception corresponds to it; nor have we any idea what a theory would be like that enabled us to conceive of it. 13
  • 25. Very little work has been done on the basic question (from which mention of the brain can be entirely omitted) whether any sense can be made of experiences' having an objective character at all. Does it make sense, in other words, to ask what my experiences are really like, as opposed to how they appear to me? We cannot genuinely understand the hypothesis that their nature is captured in a physical description unless we understand the more fundamental idea that they have an objective nature (or that objective processes can have a subjective nature). 14 I should like to close with a speculative proposal. It may be possible to approach the gap between subjective and objective from another direction. Setting aside temporarily the relation between the mind What is it like to be a bat http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html 7 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12 and the brain, we can pursue a more objective understanding of the mental in its own right. At present we
  • 26. are completely unequipped to think about the subjective character of experience without relying on the imagination—without taking up the point of view of the experiential subject. This should be regarded as a challenge to form new concepts and devise a new method—an objective phenomenology not dependent on empathy or the imagination. Though presumably it would not capture everything, its goal would be to describe, at least in part, the subjective character of experiences in a form comprehensible to beings incapable of having those experiences. We would have to develop such a phenomenology to describe the sonar experiences of bats; but it would also be possible to begin with humans. One might try, for example, to develop concepts that could be used to explain to a person blind from birth what it was like to see. One would reach a blank wall eventually, but it should be possible to devise a method of expressing in objective terms much more than we can at present, and with much greater precision. The loose intermodal analogies—for example, 'Red is like the sound of a trumpet'—which crop up in discussions of this subject are of little use. That should be clear to anyone who has both heard a trumpet and seen red. But
  • 27. structural features of perception might be more accessible to objective description, even though something would be left out. And concepts alternative to those we learn in the first person may enable us to arrive at a kind of understanding even of our own experience which is denied us by the very ease of description and lack of distance that subjective concepts afford. Apart from its own interest, a phenomenology that is in this sense objective may permit questions about the physically basis of experience to assume a more intelligible form. Aspects of subjective experience that admitted this kind of objective description might be better candidates for objective explanations of a more familiar sort. But whether or not this guess is correct, it seems unlikely that any physical theory of mind can be contemplated until more thought has been given to the general problem of subjective and objective. Otherwise we cannot even pose the mind-body problem without sidestepping it. NOTES: 1 Examples are J. J. C. Smart, Philosophy and Scientific Realism (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1963); David K.
  • 28. Lewis, 'An Argument for the Identity Theory', Journal of Philosophy, LXIII (1966), reprinted with addenda in David M. Rosenthal, Materialism & the Mind-Body Problem, (Engelwood Cliffs, NJ.: Prentice-Hall, 1971); Hilary Putnam, 'Psychological Predicates', in Art, Mind, & Religion, ed. W. H. Capitan and D. D. Merrill (Pittsburgh: University of Pittsburgh Press, 1967), reprinted in Materialism, ed. Rosenthal, as 'The Nature of Mental States'; D. M. Armstrong, A Materialist Theory of the Mind (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1968); D. C. Dennett, Content and Consciousness (London: Routledge & Kegan Paul, 1969). I have expressed earlier doubts in 'Armstrong on the Mind', Philosophical Review, LXXIX (1970), 394-403; a review of Dennett, Journal of Philosophy, LXIX (1972); and chapter 11 above. See also Saul Kripke, 'Naming and Necessity'. in Semantics of Natural Language, ed. D. Davidson and G. Harman (Dordrecht: Reidel, 1972), esp. pp. 334-42; and M. T. Thornton, 'Ostensive Terms and Materialism', The Monist, LVI (1972), 193-214. 2 Perhaps there could not actually be such robots. Perhaps anything complex enough to behave like a person would have experiences. But that, if true, is a fact which cannot be discovered merely by analyzing the concept of experience.
  • 29. 3 It is not equivalent to that about which we are incorrigible, both because we are not incorrigible about experience and because experience is present in animals lacking language and thought, who have no beliefs at all about their experiences. 4 Cf. Richard Rorty, 'Mind-Body Identity, Privacy, and Categories', Review of Metaphysics, XIX (1965), esp. 37-8. 5 By 'our own case' I do not mean just 'my own case', but rather the mentalistic ideas that we apply unproblematically to ourselves and other human beings. 6 Therefore the analogical form of the English expression 'what it is like' is misleading. It does not mean 'what (in our experience) it resembles', but rather 'how it is for the subject himself'. What is it like to be a bat http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html 8 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12 7 Any intelligent extraterrestrial beings totally different from us.
  • 30. 8 It may be easier than I suppose to transcend inter-species barriers with the aid of the imagination. For example, blind people are able to detect objects near them by a form of sonar, using vocal clicks or taps of a cane. Perhaps if one knew what that was like, one could by extension imagine roughly what it was like to possess the much more refined sonar of a bat. The distance between oneself and other persons and other species can fall anywhere on a continuum. Even for other persons the understanding of what it is like to be them is only partial, and when one moves to species very different from oneself, a lesser degree of partial understanding may still be available. The imagination is remarkably flexible. My point, however, is not that we cannot know what it is like to be a bat. I am not raising that epistemological problem. My point is rather that even to form a conception of what it is like to be a bat (and a fortiori to know what it is like to be a bat) one must take up the bat's point of view. If one can take it up roughly, or partially, then one's conception will also be rough or partial. Or so it seems in our present state of understanding. 9 The problem I am going to raise can therefore be posed even if the distinction between more subjective and more
  • 31. objective descriptions or viewpoints can itself be made only within a larger human point of view. I do not accept this kind of conceptual relativism, but it need not be refuted to make the point that psychophysical reduction cannot be accommodated by the subjective-to-objective model from other cases. 10 The problem is not just that when I look at the Mona Lisa, my visual experience has a certain quality, no trace of which is to be found by someone looking into my brain. For even if he did observe there a tiny image of the Mona Lisa, he would have no reason to identify it with the experience. 11 The relation would therefore not be a contingent one, like that of a cause and its distinct effect. It would be necessarily true that a physical state felt a certain way. Saul Kripke in Semantics of Natural Language, (ed. Davidson and Harman) argues that causal behaviorist and related analyses of the mental fail because they construe, e.g., 'pain' as a merely contingent name of pains. The subjective character of an experience ('its immediate phenomenolocal quality' Kripke calls it (p. 340)) is the essential property left out by such analyses, and the one in virtue of which it is, necessarily, the experience it is. My view is closely related to his. Like Kripke, I find the hypothesis that a certain
  • 32. brain state should necessarily have a certain subjective character incomprehensible without further explanation. No such explanation emerges from theories which view the mind- brain relation as contingent, but perhaps there are other alternatives, not yet discovered. A theory that explained how the mind-brain relation was necessary would still leave us with Kripke's problem of explaining why it nevertheless appears contingent. That difficulty seems to me surmountable, in the following way. We may imagine something by representing it to ourselves either perceptually, sympathetically, or symbolically. I shall not try to say how symbolic imagination works, but part of what happens in the other two cases is this. To imagine something perceptually, we put ourselves in a conscious state resembling the state we would be in if we perceived it. To imagine something sympathetically, we put ourselves in a conscious state resembling the thing itself. (This method can be used only to imagine mental events and stares—our own or another's.) When we try to imagine a mental state occurring without its associated brain state, we first sympathetically imagine the occurrence of the mental state: that is, we put ourselves into a state that resembles it mentally. At the same time, we attempt perceptually to imagine the
  • 33. nonoccurrence of the associated physical state, by putting ourselves into another state unconnected with the first; one resembling that which we would be in if we perceived the nonoccurrence of the physical state. Where the imagination of physical features is perceptual and the imagination of mental features is sympathetic, it appears to us that we can imagine any experience occurring without its associated brain state, and vice versa. The relation between them will appear contingent even if it is necessary, because of the independence of the disparate types of imagination. (Solipsism incidentally, results if one misinterprets sympathetic imagination as if it worked like perceptual imagination: it then seems impossible to imagine any experience that is not one's own.) 12 See 'Mental Events' in Experience and Theory, ed. Lawrence Foster and J. W. Swanson (Amherst: University of Massachusetts Press, 1970); though I do not understand the argument against psychophysical laws. 13 Similar remarks apply to my paper 'Physicalism', Philosophical Review, LXXIV (1965), 339-56, reprinted with postscript in Modern Materialism, ed. John O'Connor (New York: Harcourt Brace Jovanovich, 1969).
  • 34. 14 This question also lies at the heart of the problem of other minds, whose close connection with the mind-body problem is often overlooked. If one understood how subjective experience could have an objective nature, one would What is it like to be a bat http://members.aol.com/NeoNoetics/Nagel_Bat.html 9 of 9 20/04/2004 16.12 understand the existence of subjects other than oneself. 15 I have not defined the term 'physical'. Obviously it does not apply just to what can be described by the concepts of contemporary physics, since we expect further developments. Some may think there is nothing to prevent mental phenomena from eventually being recognized as physical in their own right. But whatever else may be said of the physical, it has to be objective. So if our idea of the physical ever expands to include mental phenomena, it will have to assign them an objective character—whether or not this is done by analyzing them in terms of other phenomena already regarded as physical It seems to me more likely, however, that mental-physical relations will eventually be expressed in a theory whose fundamental terms cannot be
  • 35. placed clearly in either category.