Practicing Intelligence Providing Support To Combat Operations 1st Timothy Oliver
Practicing Intelligence Providing Support To Combat Operations 1st Timothy Oliver
Practicing Intelligence Providing Support To Combat Operations 1st Timothy Oliver
Practicing Intelligence Providing Support To Combat Operations 1st Timothy Oliver
1. Practicing Intelligence Providing Support To
Combat Operations 1st Timothy Oliver download
https://ebookbell.com/product/practicing-intelligence-providing-
support-to-combat-operations-1st-timothy-oliver-33718698
Explore and download more ebooks at ebookbell.com
3. PRACTICING INTELLIGENCE
PROVIDING SUPPORT TO COMBAT OPERATIONS
TIMOTHY J. OLIVER
CLARENDON RESEARCH & ANALYSIS PRESS
3100 Clarendon BLVD, STE 200, Arlington, VA 22201
5. In memory of
Major Ricardo A. Crocker, USMCR
February 25, 1966–May 26, 2005
Killed in Action, Haditha, Iraq
Semper Fidelis
6. ACKNOWLEDGEMENTS
I would like to thank the following colleagues and friends for their invaluable
assistance and guidance in this effort: Dr. Jennifer Deal, Brigadier General
Paul Laughlin USA Retired, Colonel Ken Nugent, USAF Retired, Colonel
Wayne Barefoot USA Retired, from whom I “borrowed” several phrases, and
Kelly Kowal from Clarendon Research & Analysis for her forbearance. Most
importantly I would like to offer my deepest gratitude to those I have had the
privilege to serve with and who taught me the lessons that I have tried to pass
on here.
7. FOREWORD
You grow or you die. You are either learning or forgetting, improving or
degrading. The point at which you believe you have mastered a task, skill, or
body of knowledge is the point at which your decline begins. There is no
stasis, no plateau.
Nowhere is this principle more true than in the intelligence profession,
where failure to grow and anticipate changes in the operating environment,
technology, and trade craft will eventually lead to surprise and failure—
potentially catastrophic failure.
With this idea in mind, the purpose of this book is to help the reader grow
in the practice of intelligence. It is designed as an aid to thinking broadly and
critically about the profession, as well as to help challenge and continuously
refine the intelligence professional’s assumptions about training, organizing,
and executing support to combat operations.
Practicing Intelligence comprises a series of principles, notes on practical
application, and considerations related to the practice of intelligence. It seeks
to fill the gap between doctrine and training and the day-to-day practice of
the trade. Accordingly, it covers both larger concepts and more mundane
aspects of functioning effectively within the intelligence bureaucracy.
While it may have some applicability to a general audience or the broader
intelligence community, it was written for Marines and soldiers. Specifically,
the junior enlisted and officers in the intelligence field. It is written from their
perspective and with their circumstances in mind.
A note on research and doctrine:
This is not a research project. There are some references, a few random
quotes, and some mnemonics cut-and-pasted from the Internet, but it is
8. almost entirely a collection of observations and principles distilled from one
Marine’s experience. It is, for better or worse, a product of lived experience.
This is also not a doctrinal publication. It is replete with non-doctrinal
terminology and the author’s idiosyncratic usage. The intent, however, is not
to contradict existing doctrine or offer alternatives. The non-doctrinal
language is intended solely to foster a broader and more intuitive
understanding of intelligence, and to help the reader think more critically
about the how and the why of things.
Accordingly, it should be viewed as a companion to and not as a
replacement for Professional Military Education (PME) or existing doctrine.
9. CONTENTS
1. A Framework
Defining Intelligence
Tools
2. Principles for the Practice of Intelligence
3. Practical Application
Briefing
Writing
Analysis
Leading intelligence
Organizing for Intelligence
Collecting
Relationships and red cells
Expeditionary Intelligence
Law
Tactics, Techniques and Philosophies
4. Points for Consideration
Truth and Consequences
Information as a weapon
The Use and Misuse of History
Conflict as the Enemy
The Future
13. DEFINING INTELLIGENCE
“The necessity of procuring good Intelligence is apparent & need not be
further urged.” – George Washington
Let’s begin with an elephant. Most readers will be familiar with the parable
of the blind men and the elephant. Each blind man is touching a part of the
elephant, the tail, a foot, the trunk, an ear. Each of those parts feels like a very
different thing. It is only when the blind men share their impressions that they
can “see” the elephant.
This is a crude but apt metaphor for the practice of intelligence. If the blind
men (the different members of the intelligence team, signals intelligence,
human intelligence, all-source analysis, etc.) don’t work together, they won’t
see the elephant—the enemy, the other side of Wellington’s Hill.
Your function as an intelligence professional is to see the elephant, ideally
before it steps on you. When in doubt about what you should do or where
your priorities should lie, remember this and proceed accordingly.
WHAT INTELLIGENCE IS AND WHAT IT DOES
Intelligence is knowledge or understanding of the enemy or operating
environment that conveys an informational advantage to the possessor.
Intelligence provides informational advantage as maneuver provides
positional advantage.
Intelligence avoids surprise by getting there first. Surprise is failure—
surprise means that intelligence has failed.
14. Better intelligence or informational advantage ideally results in better
decisions. The author employs the caveat “ideally” here to highlight the fact
that intelligence and decision are not the same thing. Of this, more later.
Informational advantage is the ultimate purpose of an intelligence
professional, and all his or her actions should be measured against this
standard. Find the IED before it finds you. Better yet, before it is laid.
PRODUCING INTELLIGENCE
In the simplest terms, intelligence is produced by sensing and evaluating,
which are the first two steps of the traditional decision cycle: Sense, Evaluate,
Decide, Act (SEDA).
This is roughly equivalent to the first steps of the doctrinal Intelligence
Cycle: Plan, Direct, Collect, Process, Analyze, and Disseminate.
Everyone of course runs through the SEDA cycle on a continuous basis in
the conduct of both their personal and professional lives. The practice of
intelligence diverges from the informal process of Sensing and Evaluating in
its planned and deliberate nature. This is described in the Planning and
Directing steps of the Intelligence Cycle.
A more intuitive way to understand the Intelligence Cycle is in the
following series of steps:
Determine what information is needed.
Acquire that information (through collection and analysis).
Ensure that information is understood by those who need it.
Counter the enemy’s ability to gain informational advantage over
you.
15. You will note that the above steps closely adhere to the traditional
intelligence cycle, with the exception of the last step. This final step refers to
counterintelligence or those actions designed to detect and deny an
adversary’s intelligence efforts against you. Why does the author include it
here if his purpose is not to challenge doctrine? Because it is important and
needs to be emphasized. You must play both offense, gathering intelligence
on the adversary, and defense, defending your critical information against
collection. To borrow from the now (mostly) defunct KGB, you must be the
sword and the shield.
To summarize, intelligence is informational advantage, and the function of
the intelligence professional is to provide it by determining what information
is needed, acquiring that information, and making sure it is understood—all
while keeping the enemy from doing the same.
WHAT INTELLIGENCE IS NOT (OR MOSTLY
SHOULD NOT BE)
Intelligence is not cable news. For starters, that market is already saturated
by better-resourced organizations. Creating your own is redundant and time-
consuming. You can’t compete and you shouldn’t try because this is not your
purpose. The news is about things that have already happened—or, in the
current age, endless editorializing. If the focus of your day is running to the
boss with current events, you are missing the point of informational
advantage. Also, it’s likely that the boss has a TV in his or her office, so you
are going to be late anyways. Your focus, and the rest of the intelligence
team’s, should be on what is going to happen next—what is going to happen
tomorrow, next week, over the coming five or ten years, over the next hill.
The intelligence professional does not exist to answer questions (humor the
author here). It is of course your job to know things, and if you have any skill
16. or desire to have any credibility there will be some expectation that you be
something of a walking encyclopedia. Being so is always useful for building
trust and influence with the customer. But let us return to the concept of
informational advantage. You should be looking to the future. You have to be
anticipatory—not just about the enemy and the operating environment, but
also about the requirements of friendly forces. If you are being asked a
question, that is an indicator that you failed to anticipate the need for that
information.
You are not the Shitty Little Jobs Officer (SLJO). Intelligence is too
important to be superseded by urinalysis, voter registration, collecting plaque
and flower funds, or inventorying the armory. That, of course, is a test to see
if you are awake. You are the SLJO. What sets you apart from the
infantryman or the aircrewman is not your specialness but your mission.
Theirs is to locate and close with the enemy, or keep a helicopter from falling
out of the sky. Yours is to provide them with the informational advantage to
succeed at theirs.
So, you are the SLJO. You are in the boat with everyone else, and you must
row like everyone else. You are a Marine or soldier first and “all things
thereunto pertaining.” You must do them well. If you have questions about
this, refer to “Leadership Traits and Principles” in the next section or your
SgtMaj or Senior Enlisted Advisor.
17. TOOLS
A tool is a device used to help perform a job. What follows is a collection
of the most common and useful tools for intelligence work. Luckily, these are
tools you are probably already familiar with: Memory aids, rules of thumb,
acronyms. Since you stood on the yellow footprints at the Recruit Depot, you
have likely been required to memorize simple formulas and phrases to help
you remember important concepts and procedures. You may be of the
opinion that you have evolved beyond the use of these crude instruments. At
this very instant you may be stalking the halls of power offering sage counsel
to very important people or engaged in activities of such technical
sophistication that you feel these simple tools are of no use to you. If you
believe this, you believe wrongly.
These tools remain invaluable regardless of your position or level of
professional development. They help organize your thoughts, check your
work, and quickly and critically evaluate the most complicated of problems.
They are particularly useful when you must generate assessments quickly,
and in your chosen profession that can be while literally under fire. Most
importantly, they help you avoid making mistakes of omission.
They are included here because they are the intelligence professional’s most
fundamental and useful tools for critical thinking and are therefore worth
revisiting. So, take time to review them. Post them in your cubicle, laminate
them and take them to the field, commit them to memory, and add new ones
as you find them.
LEADERSHIP
18. We start with a tool not specific to intelligence. Specifically, The
Leadership Traits and Principles. Why leadership traits and principles in a
book about intelligence? Because leadership matters in intelligence as it does
everywhere else.
Leadership and management theories proliferate like good ideas at higher
headquarters and few other things in the culture. Cheese gets moved, stuff
gets disrupted, and new books about a special “way of leadership” are
generated at the cyclic rate. These are all fine, the author is sure. Read them
at your leisure and apply them if they work for you.
But, luckily for you, the author has a more practical purpose in mind and no
new leadership theories to peddle. Rather, we revisit ones the reader should
already know. The very same ones the you started with in Basic Training or
Officer Candidate School. They were good enough when written, they are
good enough now, and they will be good enough on whatever future
battlefield you find yourself.
They will reappear throughout the remainder of this book, your career, and
for the rest of your life. So, let us review.
LEADERSHIP TRAITS (otherwise known as JJDTIEBUCKLE)
Justice
Judgment
Dependability
Tact
Integrity
Enthusiasm
Bearing
Unselfishness
20. analogically to an expression which we before made use of, we may term
poetry the mind’s transcendent recollection of the eternal. For the first and
most ancient poetry, as the common memory of the human race—its higher
organ of remembrance—passes on from century to century, and from nation
to nation; and though ever dressing itself in the changing fashion of the day,
yet, through all time, it refers us back to the primary and eternal.
Music, on the other hand, is eminently an art of longing. To this it owes
all its ravishing enchantments—its magic and irresistible charms. In music,
however, as in every other form of art, the higher and the earthly—the soul,
as it were, and the body—the heavenly longing and the terrestrial are often
blended together in the same note and tone, so as scarcely to be
discriminated. It is this mingling of feelings and emotions—where from
amid the half-unconscious earthly longing a higher and more heavenly
aspiration gleams out, that in youth, when man’s sensibility is first
developed and expanded, gives to newly-waking love its peculiar magic
charm, the inner grace of the youthful soul contributing as much if not more
than even the bloom of corporeal beauty. The question, indeed, whether in
this youthful longing really a higher love of eternal duration, as an inner
light, which is continually purifying and perfecting itself, be inclosed within
the earthly veil—whether this first love of youth be even the true love, or
whether all may have been nothing more than the transient and flickering
flame of a delusion—this question can be alone determined from its results;
in other words, by the life which proceeds and follows from it. It must be
proved by the unwavering truth and fidelity—I might almost say, the
inward truth of the heart and the outward character of the whole life; and, in
short, of a higher love in its every species, whether human or divine.
Now this longing holds a most important place in man. Not only is it the
crisis of transition from childish, shall we say consciousness or
unconsciousness, into a more mature development—not only is it the
threshold under which youthful expectation enters on a fuller and more
perfect life; but also still surviving uninterruptedly to the end, it ever
remains the first, strongest, and purest impulse of the inner man. The light
of its never-dying flame, growing purer and stronger, lights him on his way
to a higher and better existence. It seems, therefore, not out of place to add
here the remark, how deeply hope, which is so closely associated with this
longing aspiration, is interwoven into the very being of man, so as almost to
form the characteristic peculiarity of his inner life and whole state.
21. The lost spirits, we are told, “believe and tremble.”[68] Love, too, is the
essential property of God, and even his very essence, and in a certain sense,
also, it is common to all beings created by eternal love. Even in the hidden
veins of life, through all animated nature, beats this pulse of universal love.
Hope, however, can not be ascribed to God, for in Him all is full and
perfect. Nature can only sigh and bemoan itself; and even though it be not
hopelessly wretched, yet, properly, it can not hope for aught, by its own
power, at least. To man, above all other created beings, belongs the
prerogative of hope. We might almost call him an immortal spirit, subjected
to the condition of hope. And so, before the rest of creation, he is destined
and chosen to be the evangelist of divine hope.
As the third of the inner life-springs of true art and higher poetry, I spoke
of a true enthusiasm and inspired feeling of the divine. Now, among the
various arts, I would especially appropriate this to the plastic art—in that
widest and justest sense of the term, in which it comprises, also, the higher
architecture. For, in enthusiasm and inspiration, the divinity with which it is
imbued is not viewed and contemplated in the remote distance either of the
past or the future. It is embraced at once as something actual and present.
And this holds good both of the enthusiasm of art, and also of that which, in
moral and political life, often creates for itself an epoch, shaping and
bringing forth whatever is truly new and original. Now, the divine in beauty
must be actually present to the mind, at least, of the artist. It must have
stood vividly before his mental eye before it could have come forth in
outward and visible form. Since universally the perfection of art depends on
some antagonism and the artist’s triumph over it, it is self-evident that even
here the most exalted enthusiasm must be associated with a thoughtful
sagacity and persevering steadiness of execution, if any great and perfect
work is to be produced. Moreover, it can scarcely be necessary to remind
you that the arts, even though, perhaps, in each of them there is a
predominance of some peculiar kind of higher feeling, or some spirit of
higher life swells out in it, are not, therefore, rigidly limited on all sides and
irrevocably confined within these narrow limits. On the contrary, one
branch of art often passes over into the domain of another. And this
interference is not always a misconception, owing chiefly to some
confusion of essential matters, and, therefore, in the highest degree
erroneous and prejudicial. Poetry, especially, often springs up indigenous in
other domains of art, being the most universal of all. And if in poetry itself
22. those ancient and primitive poems or epic songs of sublime recollections
occupy the first place, who, therefore, would exclude from it the deep,
inner, ardent longing—the oracular faculty of divination for exalted love
and eternal hope, with all its music of the feelings, forming, as it does, the
spiritual contents, the animating principle and distinctive essence of the
lyrical art? Who, too, would dare to censure poetry, because, striving to give
another and a newer expression to all that, in these divine remembrances
and longing anticipations, constitutes its inmost soul, it attempts, by
dramatic representation, to portray the essential features of its inmost being,
with all the vivid reality and distinct completeness of the present? For does
it not, in this respect, approximate, so far, at least, to the plastic arts, and
begin to assume many points of affinity with them?
It is, however, necessary to guard here against a possible
misunderstanding. Not without good cause, I believe, before all things is the
rigid discrimination insisted on which must separate true poetry from a
spurious semblance. Poetry which condescends to minister either to the
passions or to fashion, or even to prose, or any mere prosaic ends, can not
deserve the name. But it is another thing when the poet works his poetical
view of things (and this is that which constitutes the poet, and not the mere
outward form of poetry alone) into the prosaic reality of some present time,
or some historical subject. So, too, is it when in some consistent and artistic
imitation of life he takes for his theme the maze of human passions, by no
means for the purpose of prolonging it, and still less of inflaming it, but
rather because he clearly sees through its complications, to unfold and
disentangle them. This we might call—employing a term belonging to the
mathematical sciences, though in a different but still analogous sense—
mixed or applied poetry; and to this class belong many of the highest
productions of art in different ages and nations.
The different arts, or, rather, the different directions of one and the same
art, in the several epochs and ages of the world, or among nations variously
divided by language and manners, as well as by the style and character of
their thought and intellect, may be considered as merely so many varying
dialects of one and the same language, which have a common origin and are
nearly related. For they possess a common meaning, which, interpreted by a
profound and noble perception of art, will be found to pervade all centuries
and all people, uniting and enchaining them all by this soul-binding tie of a
loving and love-kindled fancy. These eternal and fundamental feelings of
23. the human breast, the remembrance of eternity, an innate longing and high-
soaring aspiration, stand in the most intimate connection with each other,
even though we can not take a full survey of it, and often feel it profoundly
rather than are able perfectly to explain it. They are like so many stem-
words and radical syllables, and form together, as it were, one common
language. And if, as I before remarked, we should in vain seek for that
common and original language, from which all those now spoken on the
face of the earth can be derived, both ethnographically and geologically,
may we not still find in art a universal language intelligible to all men? Is
not this language (as I may term it) thus enveloped in the garb of art,
through which, however, a profound significance gleams brightly forth, an
original language of a higher and intellectual order, and at the same time
intimately akin with our own nature? Do not its echoes, however faint and
broken, when reawakened by true art and sublime poetry, strike a chord of
unison in every human breast?
LECTURE V.
THE general notion of the inner life formed the point from which we
started in this attempt to portray the whole spiritual man. I maintained, you
will remember, that the philosophy of life proceeds on the simple
assumption of this inner life. Now, in the preceding discourses it has been
my endeavor to unfold this general idea into a more fully-developed and
more definite conception of human consciousness, both in its several
principles and total coherence. And this almost completes the first division
of our whole sketch. For fully to complete a knowledge of ourselves, and of
life in general, a few particulars only remain to be added, and a
comprehensive review of the whole once more to be taken. And this, in the
natural order of this simple development of thought, forms the next subject
of our labors. By reason of the close vital connection which subsists
between thought and speech, language served in the first instance for an
external basis of comparison, which in the next place art enabled me to
carry still farther, inasmuch as the latter may also be regarded as an inner
language. For, however fragmentary and incomplete may be our collection
of languages and the science thereof, notwithstanding all the enlargement it
has received from modern observation and research, it is still possible, by a
rigorous distinction of the derivatory and mixed offshoots from the more
24. ancient and purer branches, to gain at least an insight into the history and
progress of language, and thence to trace the probable course of its
development, even while its origin, no less than the equally
incomprehensible phenomenon of its first exercise, remains veiled in
impenetrable obscurity. And when we called art a language, we did not
mean this merely in the same sense that poetry has been styled—and indeed
has even herself assumed the title of—a divine language, on account of the
ornamental figures of its external form; neither was it because of the
allegorical shapes and allusions, nor of the symbolical garb which plastic
art so often puts on. The so transiently advanced metaphor was intended to
convey the idea that art in general, not merely in its outward form, but in its
inmost essence, and in all of its forms and species alike, is a language of
nature of a higher and spiritual kind, or, if the term be preferred, an inward
hieroglyphical writing and original speech of the soul, which is immediately
intelligible to all susceptible natures, and to every one whose sensibilities a
taste for any form of art has rendered open and accessible to its appeal. For
the key to it lies not in any arbitrarily established principle, as is the case
with that ingenious and beautiful, but still merely conventional invention of
the East—the symbolical language of flowers, but in the feeling and the
soul itself. For the eternal and fundamental feelings of the soul are
awakened, or, rather, reawakened, in these inner-soul words of true art,
which, in the same sense that we speak of the riddle of life or of the world,
making its solution the object and aim of philosophy, we may likewise term
a riddle of hope—of that hope, in truth, which is eternal and divine. But
high art, like life and the world, remains a riddle, and must ever appear to
us as such, simply because in reality, or at least for the greater part, it is
only a few detached notes, without the full and coherent air, that it allows to
reach us.
There is, then, an intrinsic connection between thought and speech,
between language and consciousness. Moreover man, to judge of him by
the collective sum of his characteristic and essential properties, is nothing
else than the created word, the faint echo and very imperfect copy of the
uncreated and eternal, and stands amid the rest of creation, midway between
the world of nature and that of spirits. For these reasons, then, in the further
exposition of his inner life I shall invariably make use of the idea of
language, and even many of its characteristic properties or peculiarities, as
the external basis of a comparison calculated to throw light upon much that
25. in the inward thought of man it is otherwise difficult to express and to make
clear by words. For, indeed, generally, living thought and the science
thereof, can not well or easily be separated from the philosophy of
language.
The general idea of the inner life was, I said, the basis of all the previous
development of ideas, and this was the only hypothesis which a philosophy
of life stands in need of, or can venture to assume. An objection may, it is
true, be here started. In the various digressions into which, in the further
development of this one fundamental thought, I have been led by my wish
to expand it to a full and complete idea of the consciousness, it may be said
that much besides has been supposed or taken for granted, if not expressly,
yet tacitly; not indeed arbitrarily, but still as the result of a merely personal
conviction, however positive and deliberate. To this objection, so naturally
to be expected, I can only reply, that if occasionally I may not have
expressed myself hypothetically enough, it was, nevertheless, my intention
so to do. Consequently all hypothetical positions, with the exception of the
fundamental one of the inner thought and life, hitherto assumed by me, are
to be regarded here simply in such a light. They are advanced only for the
nonce, and provisionally, until they can receive a further and completer
analysis, without in anywise anticipating the proof, nor, by a hasty decision,
assuming the truth, as if it were independent of argument.
Now, since doubt is a necessary and inevitable property and an essential
principle of the whole man in his present state, we are brought by the
regular course of our analysis to the problem which is furnished by the
thought at issue with itself. To this subject, which now forces itself
immediately on our attention, we must devote an entire section of our
labors. The object of the first portion was to advance the simple and general
thought of the inner life (as being in this simple generality too vague and
undefined), or to raise it, step by step, to a full, complete, and
comprehensive, but at the same time rightly divided conception of the
human mind. In the same way, in the next division of my speculations, the
essential subject and proper aim will be to carry that feeling, call it as we
will, whether of pure love, or inner life, or higher truth, whose existence we
have, we think, clearly established, through the crisis of doubt, to a
determinate judgment of profound certainty and unwavering conviction, or
at least to a rigorous distinction between that which is certain and that
which must forever remain uncertain.
26. Now, to render in any degree complete that characteristic of the human
mind which it has been our object or endeavor in the previous Lectures to
sketch in detail, we were obliged to take in also those higher elements
which by many are called in question, and by some positively denied to
exist. And herein lay the natural ground and the occasion for our
introducing the mention of them, at least as facts of consciousness generally
acknowledged by the common-sense of mankind. Not that we thereby
meant to exclude them from a profounder investigation, or to guard them
against the intrusion of that doubt which knows no limits to its skepticism.
We only reserved them to their appropriate place in the natural course of
our development of living thought. Some there are, we know, who hold
even a higher and genuine sense of art to be a mere fancy either of genius,
devoted to and displaying its excellence therein, or of the mere dilettanti.
Others again, and even celebrated writers, have explained conscience and
its still, small voice, by the acquired or instilled prejudice of education, or
as the delusive effect of custom. How far more numerous, then, must be the
doubts which such a system of abnegation of all that is good and exalted
would raise against the Platonic doctrine of a recollection of eternal love, or
that idea which I have labored to establish, of a pure longing after infinity!
If, again, many question the freedom of the will, they deny, in fact, the will
itself; for a will that is not free ceases to be will. If, moreover, others refuse
to recognize in all human thought, fictions, and inventions, any thing
creatively new and peculiarly original, seeing therein nothing but repetition
or fresh combinations of external impressions, consequently denying to the
human mind all power of invention, then must fancy be denied to be one of
the mind’s fundamental powers. For, in truth, in such a case, it is nothing
more than memory, or, rather, it is memory fallen into delirium. Others,
again, would refer even reason itself and the essential rational character of
man simply to a more delicate sensuous organization than is possessed by
the most highly-endowed among the brute creation. All such special and
eccentric opinions form but so many subordinate chapters of our second
part, which has for its theme reason and doubt, and the state of doubt, which
are natural to man. To it, therefore, they must be reserved for investigation.
We can not anticipate the period of their discussion in the present place,
where our first object is, by a development of the simple thought and the
general ideas of the inner life, to sketch a perfect outline of the human
27. mind, which shall take in all its higher elements and capacities, as well as
the earthly and inferior ingredients which are blended with them.
The thought or conception, as the general manifestation of the inner life,
is in its nature and form indefinite, but still a cogitation, which even at this
step is already referred to a particular object, and so in its contents limited
thereto. An idea or notion, however, is a conception mathematically
proportioned by number, measure, and weight; i.e., according to the number
of its several constituents it is carefully divided, and its subordinate genera
enumerated; measured according to its extent, and according to its internal
value and comprehension, and also its relation to other kindred notions of a
higher or lower order carefully weighed and pondered; in short, a
conception complete and perfect in itself. Hitherto, therefore, it has been
properly but a single notion that has engaged our attention, and formed the
subject-matter of our whole speculation—the notion, viz., of the human
consciousness. For it is not merely philosophy to link together in a never-
ending chain its own self-derived and arbitrary ideas, by some specious rule
of necessary connection. The duty of philosophy is rather originally to
combine facts—and, in truth, all the given facts of a certain kind, and
within a certain range, in one clear, intelligible, and perfectly vivid notion,
and it has generally to do with very few ideas. Two or three ideas, in short,
such as that of consciousness, of science, or of man himself, are quite
sufficient for its purpose of solving, if not fully and completely, yet at least
to the full extent of what is not merely possible and allowable, but also
wholesome and profitable, the three riddles of life, of the universe, and of a
divine hope, which lie before the whole human mind, and thereby to arrive
at some abiding conviction with regard to them.
Now, in concluding our development of the human mind, and adding to
it all that is still wanting to its completeness, I shall observe the same
method of exposition as I have hitherto followed. Leaving for the nonce
unmooted, the grave questions whether there be any such thing as truth—
and, if so, whether man is capable of recognizing and attaining to it in any
degree—and reserving them to their appropriate place where they will
naturally arise, I shall adopt into the outline of the general notion of the
consciousness all those facts of it which are acknowledged by the common-
sense of mankind. I shall, as such, allow them all and no more than their
due weight. Occasionally, however, when any such phenomenon appears
somewhat questionable, I shall add a word or two of explanation, in order to
28. guard against the possibility of misconception, or an overhasty inference,
setting down the facts purely as such, and so far as they are already
apprehended, for further investigation and inquiry.
The four opposite poles or extremes of man’s divided and discordant
consciousness are, I said, its four fundamental faculties or powers,
understanding and will, and reason and fancy. With regard to the two first,
every one may, both from internal experience of his own self and from
observation of his fellow-men, easily arrive at a conviction that they seldom
work together in perfect harmony, and that the discord is often the most
violent when either one or both of these two faculties possess more than
ordinary strength. The marked opposition between reason and fancy reveals
itself but too plainly, both in private and public life. The men of mere taste
and imagination, artistic and poetical natures (to which category, in a
somewhat loose sense, very many really belong, though the happy
exceptions of true genius be indeed rare), on the one hand; and on the other,
the men of practical reason—the utilitarians, who limit their views, more or
less, to the public advantage to be derived from this quality of practical
reason, and look with distrust to every higher flight of fancy or feeling,
form two hostile classes of men, who with difficulty comprehend each
other. At least they are seldom in a position to understand one another’s
feelings, and rightly and fairly to appreciate them. Still more rare are the
exceptions, where both these faculties and mental characters are found
united in one and the same individual.
After these four fundamental faculties of the first order, come certain
accessory functions of the second order, derived from or compounded of the
former. Of these, conscience and memory, and after them the instincts and
passions, have been described as movements of the will, passing over into
the illimitable region of the fancy, and consequently holding an
intermediate place between will and fancy. We have now to add a word or
two concerning the external senses, and therewith to complete our sketch of
the human consciousness in its present divided and distracted condition. But
previously to entering upon this topic, I would, with reference to this last-
mentioned characteristic of instinct, call your attention to a particular
species of it, which is not unimportant, but rather belongs essentially to a
complete picture of this part of the human consciousness. It will, moreover,
furnish a new instance, to show how in nature herself there lies a cause, or
at least a first occasion for many parallels of comparative psychology,
29. similar to those which have already presented themselves. I am alluding to
the artistic instincts displayed by some of the more sagacious animals, and
especially some of the industrious members of the insect tribe. These
present a remarkable affinity to human art, in which all, at least, is not the
effect of teaching. In the lower but still beautiful degrees of artistic talent,
there is much that seems instinctive in its operation, and, as it were,
unconscious and innate. True and lofty genius of art can not be here
included. It belongs, on the contrary, to a different sphere. For in it the
unconscious creative faculty is not narrowly restricted to one rigid path or
definite form, but has rather for its essential basis a productive power of
imagination, of universal range and fullness, and which, as it were, travails
in birth with the infinite.
Now this notion, thus borrowed from natural science, for the purposes of
a comparative psychology, seems well applicable to that pure feeling of
infinite longing which is the most exalted of all man’s aspirations.
According to that idea of it which I have labored to establish, we can name
this profound inward longing, which nothing earthly can ever satisfy, man’s
instinct of eternity—an instinct which often long remains, and at the first
always is perfectly unconscious of a higher vocation and divine destiny.
The external senses are in one respect the faithful organs and instruments
of the understanding in the material world, with which it makes its
experience or observations therein, and draws therefrom its experimental
science. In another point of view, they may not improperly be termed an
applied or practical fancy, which for a definite direction exercises itself on
the individual phenomena of the material world, for the copying and
reproduction of external impressions on the organs, as, e.g., of the visible
form or reduced image in the eye, is in any case nothing but an inferior
species or a collateral branch of the general faculty of productive
imagination. But that new and spiritual sense of higher potency, which in
the purely material can only develop itself as an exception, or may appear
to be veiled therein—I mean the keen appreciation by the ear of musical
tones, and the eye for picturesque beauty of form in the plastic art—can
only be regarded as a lightning-spark of fancy passing along and operating
through this external medium and conductor.
One remark seems of importance in connection with our whole subject;
at any rate it will not be superfluous, as confirming our assertion that the
threefold principle of human life in general is found repeated in its single
30. members; and though on a smaller scale, is still manifested in the same
relation. We observe, therefore, that whatever physiological, or, it may be,
anatomical reasons physiologists may have for counting five senses—and
they may be perfectly sufficient and adequate for the requisitions of
physical science, still, psychologically, it is far more accurate and also
simpler, in a philosophical sense, to limit their number to three. No doubt,
in the sensation of taste, not only a mechanical contact occurs, but there is
also a chemical decomposition of the tasted matter, by which the sensation
of sweet or bitter is produced. So, too, in smell, although no visible
evaporation takes place, still it is a fact that aëriform floating particles are
thrown off from the sensible body, and actually taken in by the sentient.
Still these are far from being adequate grounds for making of them two
independent senses. Even in the inner organic perception of one’s bodily
health and ease, and in the opposite case of pain, it is something more than
the mere mechanical contact from without that is therein sensuously
perceived. But are we disposed on this account to agree with those who
propose to divide still further the single sense of material touch, and
increase the number of the senses? We feel at once that this would be
superfluous, since all these proposed divisions are, at least in a
psychological point of view, to be regarded simply as modifications—as
branches or lower species of one and the same sense. And by the same
analogy, then, we may reckon all these material senses for one. Thus, then,
we have in all but three senses, presenting in this smaller and meaner sphere
an accurate correspondence to the triple man, and the three elements which
make up his whole being—body, soul, and spirit.
Of the outer senses, the eye is incontestably the most spiritual. The ear,
whereby we are sentient of sounds, words, and voices, and melody, and all
music, corresponds to the soul; while the sense of material feeling, which is
also destined to be the ministering organ and guardian of the health and
welfare of the body, is corporeal, and corresponds to the principle of
organic life. After the loss both of sight and hearing, the body may both be
and long continue healthy and vigorous; whereas a defect in the sense of
feeling, so soon, at least, as it became general and total, would be the
commencement of death, or at least appear to be so, since diseases
temporarily take this form. However, this third and corporeal sense of
feeling is not always entirely external and grossly material. It may develop
itself, at least by way of exception (since the sense of art in the eye and ear
31. is not universal), as a sort of intellectual perception, though still a physical
feeling of kindred life and of the inner light, which often gives rise to a
peculiar and remarkable immediate natural sense (not to call it an instinct)
for the invisible, which is enshrouded within the outward phenomena of
life. And though some would fain deny the reality of this capacity, still,
inasmuch as its existence is a matter of fact, adequately confirmed by
experience, as great, if not greater error may be committed in the opposite
direction. Because this acute natural sense does unquestionably often arrive
in a most wonderful manner at a just and right conclusion—or this instinct
make most remarkable divinations—we must not, therefore, exalt it at once
into a kind of invisible, infallible, and, as it were, omniscient oracle. For
such is not to be met with in the path of psychology, nor in the whole circle
of faculties which belong to man as man, and least of all in that critical
point of transition out of the ordinary perception of consciousness into a
complete state of unconsciousness, and from this again into a clear and
bright consciousness; which point, even on this account, seeming to stand
midway between light and shade, exhibits here and there a strong
resemblance to the world of dreams. Such, in general, is the limitation of
the human intellect, that reason, as has been already often remarked, can
never be regarded as an unerring oracle and infallible organ of truth; neither
is the clearest understanding and the most experienced artistic sense, even
in its own peculiar sphere, always unerring. Still less can either the will or
the fancy make such a claim. Even the inner voice of conscience, although
its name alludes directly to an inward knowing, and the certainty thereof,
[69] is not always and universally recognized as such an infallible guide—
otherwise many a thinker and writer on the subject would not have set up,
as necessary to explain at least some cases, the idea of a mistaken
conscience. It appears, then, that this natural sense, even where it exists in
the greatest strength and clearness, must be always regarded as an entirely
individual and peculiar gift, and can only be understood and judged of as
such. This remark involves, perhaps, the most important consideration,
which, in judging of it, we must always keep in view. Moreover, even
where it really and decidedly exists, whether in a state of complete or half-
consciousness, or in full conscious wakefulness, it always requires the
closest observation and the most watchful care before it can attain to its full
perfection; for its development must be extremely slow and gradual. In this
respect it must resemble the expansion of that high and spiritual sense of art
32. which forms a bright and luminous point within the material organ of the
ear or eye—which lies enshrouded in the external organ like a spiritual
germ, or—as we may justly term the artist’s vision as compared with that of
other men—an eye within the eye.
We have now taken a general view of the whole human mind, finding it
to comprise four great fundamental faculties of the first class, and then
certain secondary ones—viz., memory and conscience, with the appetites
and external senses, which, at least in the psychological point of view,
appear to be mixed forms or derivatives of the former. The four first are
occasionally found combined together in due proportion. When this
combination is the natural endowment of genius, they attain to their noblest
energy, and even by a lively and careful development, they often attain to a
most exquisite unity of operation. Mostly, however, we meet with a decided
preponderance and exclusive ascendency of some one, which in its external
effects is only limited and checked by the fact that it is thus isolated. The
four rarely co-operate together; and, for the most part, by their dissension
they prove checks and hindrances to each other. But not merely in the
individual and his personal life and conduct do these four fundamental
forces display such strength and vital energy in the grand development of
the whole human race; and in its history we may also observe the same fact.
Among the Greeks we recognize, distinctly and clearly, a profound and
ingenious intellect predominating in life, no less than in art and science; in
the Romans, an irresistible and sovereign force of will, reducing the world
to its subjection, and often no less gloriously imposing laws on itself; in the
Christian middle ages, the lovely devices of fancy giving its bold shapes to
life itself as well as to art; and lastly, in modern times, reason squaring
every thing to the measure of its own mind and laws, coupling often, and
associating, or, by its middle terms, equating together the remotest
elements, and not less frequently exercising a destructive energy against all,
and even against itself. Thus this ground-scheme of human consciousness,
which formed the first result of the psychological investigation of our own
selves, meets us here also on a grander scale as a part of the world’s history,
and in the large dimensions of successive ages and centuries, as the first
striking result in the history of man’s civilization during the twenty-five
centuries which, as lying nearest to our own times, we are best acquainted
with. Much as may be wanting to fill up, both in the commencement and
the middle—much, in short, as it would be necessary to add or more closely
33. to define, if it were our object to draw a universal sketch of the four
historical epochs and ages of the civilization of the world within the limits
best known to us, yet for our immediate object these mere hints are
sufficient; for they prove how, even in history, in its place each of these four
fundamental powers of man developed itself in the most decided form and
displayed a marvelous and uncontrollable energy. Here, too, we see that an
intrinsic equilibrium between these several powers forms in general but the
rare and happy exception, while on the whole it is mostly wanting. Indeed
the absence of a complete vital union and co-operation is but too painfully
felt and perceived in the history of the world.
Quite different, however, is the case with the mixed and mediate
faculties of the second rank, which are derived from the former. To these
may be applied the remark we lately made on the American tribes and
languages, in relation to that degradation of the human race so especially
noticeable in them, and its still advancing degeneracy and dismemberment.
The external senses, whose meager powers of cognition are but a sorry
make-shift for man’s mind, which in its thirst of knowledge would embrace
all existence, the Godhead, and the universe, are narrowly restricted to the
material world immediately around him. From such slight and unpromising
beginnings, science is no doubt occasionally able to evolve many a great
and noble truth. And even in the external senses themselves a feeling of art
or a clear and pure sense of nature gleams forth at times, like a little spark
of purer light. Still even here many and great impediments affect them and
their sure application. Memory, too, is on the whole little more than a
mechanical readiness, with difficulty acquired, and soon weakened and
blunted. The appetites or instincts are liable to numberless aberrations and
passionate excesses. As to conscience, there is but too much reason to fear
that it is for the most part in a state of weakness and apathy, dwarfed and
mutilated in its powers and operations. At least, the remark is no very
strange one that conscience, which has an ear as well as a small, still voice,
does not always hear very quickly, and often fails to hear very much that it
might and would do well to listen to. Whether there are not men who in this
respect may be considered perfectly deaf, is a question which can only be
answered by an accurate and specific history of human crimes, or by those
whose calling it is to study this sad and gloomy side of the picture of human
life. Such complete moral deadness as this, however, which happily forms a
rare exception in humanity, may, perhaps, be rightly regarded as a kind of
34. moral imbecility for all higher and moral sentiments, even though it is
frequently accompanied with great clearness of intellect and a high degree
of instinctive shrewdness or cunning. On the other hand, the cases are
probably rare, where the delicate moral sensibility or inward perception of
right and wrong among nobler natures, is developed in such purity and
strength, and carried to such a height of perfection and stability, as the
musical ear and artistic delicacy is by great musicians and amateurs of the
art. Probably, too, it is more suitable, and also more profitable, for human
nature in its present degraded state, that its higher senses and organs for the
invisible should not manifest themselves in us in all their extreme and
overpowering energy, and for the most part should but shine with a subdued
light, or, as it were, gleam through some shrouding envelope. Even of the
conscience this is true. At least, it admits not of denial that a few moments’
brief enjoyment of a truly bright and clear-sighted conscience would be
enough to tear the soul forever from its present indifference, and to plunge
it into an abyss of unspeakable grief, for which earthly language possesses
no adequate expression, and for which the human bosom has no suitable
notes of lamentation and mourning. It is, therefore, only the greater proof of
beneficence if the invisible world, and the mysteries of eternal woe which
await the lost spirit—in comparison with which every earthly pain and all
earthly suffering are as nothing—is in mercy shrouded with a veil, which
only seldom and on rare occasions may lawfully be lifted. Now, generally, it
is at the uttermost confines of error, in the very depths of degradation, and
the lowest level of narrow-mindedness, that the first higher impulse and
beginning of happier times exalts itself, opening out the way of return to a
newer and better life. The same probably may be the case in our present
shackled and distracted consciousness. Those very gross mistakes and
aberrations to which the limited and discordant faculties are liable, may
furnish the common basis for the growth of another vitally complete and
harmonious co-operating consciousness.
For now that we have, by the enumeration of these eight faculties, made
a complete sketch of the human consciousness, the question may arise,
naturally enough, “Which is the common center of this sphere, or what is
there found or demonstrable in this center?” It was with a view to this
question that I attempted to give a refined interpretation of the Platonic idea
of the anamnesis, taking it to mean the recollection of a higher love, not so
much in a former existence as of and from eternity. We explained it,
35. consequently, to be a species of transcendental memory. And in this sense
we justified it, demonstrating at the same time, in that other region which is
formed of man’s instinct and desires, the existence of the pure idea of
infinite longing as the highest effort of the human soul. The sense of art,
and profound feeling of natural beauty, which belong to true artistic genius,
are recognized as being in their sphere extraordinary endowments. In the
same way no one will wish to deny that the moral feeling, as the natural
expression of the inner voice of conscience, constitutes in social life the
fundamental condition and the surest foundation for all lofty and noble
sentiments. Thus feeling is that center which we were in search of, of the
otherwise divided and distracted consciousness. I might call it the moral
feeling, only then it would not be of so universal an application as it really
is. For the moral aspect constitutes only a single view and energy of the
whole, since the feeling of art, and every other kind of higher sentiment,
belongs equally to it. With much greater propriety I might term it the inner,
by way of distinction from the external and material sense of feeling. Less
clear than the understanding, and not so decided or definite as the will, with
more vitality and life than the reason, but at the same time more narrowly
limited than the fancy, the immediate sphere of individual existence—
feeling, occupies the central space between the four fundamental faculties,
as well as between the four intermediate faculties of the second order. It is
the apparently indifferent, but in truth the full and living center of
consciousness, where every vibration of all the other isolated powers meet
and cross, either neutralizing each other, or combining together into new
life and harmonious co-operation It admits, indeed, of the most various
degrees of development and of every kind of progression, from the
simplest, almost indifferent, and passive sense of mere existence, up to the
highest and self-sacrificing enthusiasm, which heeds no form or phase of
death, or up to that highest state of rapture which loses itself on the very
verge of unconsciousness. In this respect we might well say, with the poet,
“Feeling is all.” It is the center of life, and the heart of the whole, each
single and individual faculty, in and by itself, being, as compared with it,
but “noise, powder, and smoke,” “shrouding the bright empyrean.” And yet
this center of the consciousness is not, however, such as to be able, by its
inherent force and activity, to organize and regulate the whole, holding in
union all those otherwise isolated powers and states of the human mind. In
this respect it is, on the whole, passive. Indeed, viewed in a more accurate
36. light, feeling is not so much an individual and peculiar faculty as an entirely
formless and indefinite, but still vitally moved and frequently excited,
condition of the consciousness, which is to form the point of transition from
its present state of fourfold division, into the living, perfect, and
harmonious co-operation of its triple state. When reason and fancy have
ceased to be divided, being restored to oneness by the living feeling, but are
blended together in the thinking and loving soul, we have the basis on
which a restoration of the consciousness to harmony and perfection must in
every case be commenced. When the great faculty of the understanding no
longer stands aloof by itself, coldly inactive; when the strong will ceases,
by its blind obstinacy, to impede its own efforts; when the two have now
grown together into an effectual potency of the life-enlightened spirit, in
which every thought is at once an act, and every word a power (a state
which is only possible and attainable in this center of a higher love)—we
have then the second step on the path of return to the original perfection of
the consciousness.
But before I attempt to add to this scale of progression the last term
which is yet wanting, I must episodically introduce and discuss another
question. It relates to the phenomenon of judgment, which as yet has not
had its place assigned to it in the consciousness. Is it to be considered as an
independent faculty of the soul, and in what relation does it stand to the
other mental powers? Now, by judgment, in the merely logical sense,
nothing more is understood than the connecting of a predicate with a
subject. For instance, in the complete syllogism, “All men are mortal: Caius
is a man, therefore Caius is mortal,” the minor premise, where the middle or
general term is specially applied, and, consequently, predicted of an
individual, alone forms such a judgment. Now, since it is the reason that
logically connects thoughts together, it is not easy to see why this one act,
by which the predicate and subject are connected, should be separated from
all others and set up and regarded as an independent and especial faculty.
For by so doing nothing is explained, and an unnecessary addition is made
to the subdivisions (already too numerous) of the human mind and its
thinking powers. Quite otherwise, however, is it with another class of
judgments, which, in fact, are highly deserving the name. For these in their
proper sphere actually decide. And their decisions are generally regarded as
authoritative because they are based on natural talents, a practiced eye, a
multifarious and extensive experience, a long study of the matters they are
37. concerned about, which in practice render them more or less certain and
trustworthy. In this case the act of judgment is no simple function of the
thinking faculty. It is, rather, the sum of the manifold elements and spiritual
perceptions on which it exercises itself, and which it presupposes. For the
most part it is the highly complicated and composite result of many
fundamental premises. We can not, however, reckon this higher function of
judgment in any particular sphere as a peculiar mental faculty, since in such
a case a special one must needs be assumed for every one; for a right
discrimination in any one sphere does not by any means imply equal
certainty in another. Moreover, the several species and branches of the
general gift are found to exist quite separately and distinct from each other.
Since, then, the general notion of an independent faculty does not afford a
satisfactory explanation of the phenomena of judgment, we must seek it in
some other direction. And here a few examples will greatly tend to illustrate
the whole matter. How much, for instance, is comprised in a genuine artistic
judgment! It is compounded of a multitude of observations, impressions,
reflections, and emotions. And yet the opinion resulting from all these is
simply one, and definitely comprised in one simple sentence. Suppose the
opinion pronounced to be, that this or that beautiful and ancient painting is
not from the master to whom it is commonly ascribed, but belongs, rather,
to this or that other school. Of course I am not supposing the case where
such an assertion can be proved historically by documentary evidence. In
such a case the decision would turn on a matter of fact, and not on judgment
—at least, not on true artistic judgment. The judgment in question must
principally, if not entirely, be drawn from the work itself—from the style of
the handling, and similar indications, by a practiced and almost infallible
tact. So various, in short, and manifold are the observations on which such
an artistic judgment depends, that they often furnish matter for a whole
book, or, at least, for an essay. Whenever, however, it is really artistic
discernment, and not merely historical knowledge, that is involved, we
invariably meet with some one point or other which does not admit of
mathematical demonstration, and on which the ultimate decision must be
left to each man’s personal judgment, or that immediate perception which
forms a feeling of art. Most justly, therefore, does our language closely
connect the two expressions. For a true artistic judgment [Kunsturtheil] is
itself nothing else than this intuitive feeling of art [Kunstgefuhl] applied to a
special case or subject, and brought out in perfect clearness and comprised
38. in a definite shape. Just so it is in the sphere of social life with regard to the
judgment on what is proper—the feeling, in short, of propriety. Here, for
instance, it is no uncommon question whether this or that word, spoken in
some delicate posture of affairs, was really necessary, exactly what was
right to be said and thoroughly suitable, or altogether ill-chosen and
unseasonable. Or with regard to some step still in contemplation, it may be
disputed whether such or such a method be the best and the most
appropriate. How many little niceties and delicate considerations are here
involved, which a fine feeling can alone enter into! What various and
intricate contingencies, for which it is often difficult to find words
sufficiently expressive, must such a judgment take into account, in its
deliberation on such matters! And in social converse on such instances, is
not the casting-voice generally left to the acute sensibilities and quick tact
of woman?
For in all such cases the decision invariably depends upon an immediate
feeling of propriety, which, though first called forth and developed by the
social intercourse of life, is in truth original and innate. Such, indeed, it
must ever be. For where it does not exist naturally, it can never be learned
nor artificially acquired. The original want of this inward feeling can never
be replaced by any varnish of external culture, however brilliant. And the
case is also the same even in the sphere of science; for instance, in the
shrewd, searching glance by which the skillful physician takes his diagnosis
of disease; or in the clear, perspicacious sagacity which enables the judge,
in some highly complicated suit or doubtful criminal trial, to seize the right
point on which truth and justice hinge. For in judicial cases, with much that
admits of demonstrative proof, or which, as matter of fact, is unquestioned,
there is still more where nothing but this psychological penetration, long
practiced in such matters, and to which past experience has given
confidence in itself, can immediately see through all the sophistical wiles
not only of the pleadings and the skillful advocate, but also of the litigant
parties themselves, or of the crafty criminal.
The same remark applies also to a sphere, apparently, indeed, related to
the one last mentioned, but, in fact, essentially different and widely remote
from it. I allude to the unerring tact of the experienced statesman, by which
he not only penetrates, through his knowledge of mankind, the political
designs of others, but is also enabled to read the great events of the world
and their tendencies, and infallibly to seize the right moment for action.
39. In all these instances (and many others might easily be added) it is upon
an immediate perception or feeling of what is right that the decision finally
turns. And this fact is almost confessed by such expressions as a
“penetrating glance,” an “unerring tact,” and many similar ones to be found
in our own and other highly cultivated languages. Such a judgment may,
therefore, not inaptly be termed an intellectual feeling; for it implies the
existence of intellect. And this not only as an inborn natural talent, for the
special domain within which the judgment is to be exercised, but, moreover,
a certain development of the understanding, strengthened by long practice,
and confirmed by varied experience in the particular province. But still,
with this intellectual element there is invariably mixed a feeling, or
immediate perception, of what is right and just. It is this, in short, that
properly decides and makes the opinion ultimately expressed to be a
judgment. On this account I can not attribute the act of judgment
exclusively to the understanding, for the former involves something more
than the simple intellection of a single object. It comprises, at the same
time, a rigorous distinction between two objects, or a decision between yes
and no. Perhaps, therefore, the best and most perfect explanation of
judgment would be to call it an intelligent feeling of a correct
discrimination, comprised and expressed, and also communicated to others,
in a general form. The last-mentioned quality, however, does not always
belong to the judgment, since it often remains merely internal; at least, it
does not form an essential or necessary part of it.
Thus, then, this digression (though, in truth, it is not properly a
digression, since the question concerning the faculty of judgment, and the
position it occupies in the whole soul, is essentially connected with the
consideration of the latter) has again led us back to feeling, as the living
center of the entire consciousness, where all its extreme tendencies
converge and reunite. Here it is that the dull and unpromising state of calm,
contemplative indifference meets together with the highest excitement of
energetic activity, the lowest and most insignificant states of consciousness
being found there, as well as the most exalted and most sublime—the
enthusiasm that carries all before it, no less than the clear self-possession in
the spirit’s feeling of a discernment of truth, or, as I called the judgment, an
intelligent perception of what is right and just. In this advance of feeling in
the mind or spirit [geistigen] up to that height of self-possession and
clearness at which it receives the name of judgment, the former bears the
40. same relation to the latter as the mere thought, in its first vague generality,
does to the notion which I have defined to be a thought perfectly divided
into its organic members, and mathematically measured both inwardly and
outwardly—both, i.e., as to extent and comprehension.
Now, this inward feeling, taken in the full comprehensive sense of the
word, is the same as what I previously called sense, when I spoke of the
human consciousness as consisting of spirit, soul, and sense. In these
places, however, you will remember, I reserved to a future opportunity the
further and closer determination of the relation in which this general sense
stands to the other two elements of the mind. But inasmuch as the notion of
sense always carries us back to a special kind of sensation, limited and only
open to a special sphere of objects, the expression of an inward feeling
seems far more strictly appropriate to the third element of the mind. For the
term feeling, by its vague generality, comprises all objects of consciousness,
or, in other words, all kinds and species of a higher sense. Now, this higher
and all-embracing internal feeling is the starting-point from which we must
set out if we would hope to arrive at the complete reunion and living co-
operation which marks the consciousness in its original threefold state. It is
not, however, the key-stone of consummation. It is simply the foundation
on which all the rest must be built, or it is the deep fountain out of which
rich nourishment springs up on all sides for the other two elements of the
mind, viz., the soul and the spirit. The latter two, in fact, constitute the
whole essence of the inner man. Now, since the spirit is an active faculty,
while the soul, though possessed of a creative vitality, is on the whole
mostly passive, their undivided union and constant co-operation may, by
way of figure, be designated as an inner intellectual union or marriage in
the consciousness. Indeed, we might not inaptly explain man’s essence as
consisting in the spirit being wedded to its soul, and in the soul being
thereupon clothed with an organic body. But, to pursue the same metaphor:
this marriage between spirit and soul is not always a happy and harmonious
union. Whenever the soul, drawn off by every external impression and
attraction, loses itself in the manifold ways and by-ways of the material
world, or wanders to an unsafe distance with fancy, as she roams at liberty
amid the things of sense; whenever the spirit, trusting to its own inherent
powers, follows their dictates alone, and recognizes nothing above, and
disregards all that is without, itself, then this marriage is invariably
distracted by passionate discord and unquiet. Here, perhaps, as well as in
41. the external world, the words apply: “What God hath joined together, let no
man put asunder.” A complete and total divorce is indeed scarcely
conceivable, such is the coherence of the living consciousness. By death
alone is it possible to be brought about, or perhaps also by that flaming
sword of the Holy Word, which it is said pierces to the bone and marrow,
dividing soul and spirit. Where the first bond of union was given by God, it
must be maintained and continually strengthened by recurring to this
supreme center, if it is to be permanent and to look finally for perfection.
This is only possible where the spirit recognizes a divine standard above
itself, and where, in all its thoughts, works, and deeds, it acts upon this
exalted principle, and where also the soul seeks before all things this eternal
center of love, and is ever reverting to it. In such a case both soul and spirit
are united in God, or at least are ever yearning for such a union. And, in
truth, nothing more is required of man than what has always and every
where been required of him, though, alas! this requisition has seldom been
fully realized. God, then, is the keystone which holds together the whole
human consciousness; and this is the point to which our investigation has,
step by step, been leading us. And now our notion of the whole scheme and
delineation of the human mind is complete.
Its general basis and outline, such as we find it within ourselves, is
formed by the four fundamental faculties first described, together with four
others of a lower and secondary order. Feeling—i.e., the inner feeling,
comprising every higher form thereof, is its center. It is that by which we
first are awakened to its present existence, and also at the same time the
point at which we pass into a higher state, wherein its operation will be
more vivid and its union more harmonious. But as to the threefold life of
the inner man, it consists in spirit, soul, and God, as the third, in whom the
first two are united, or at least must seek their union.
In proportion, therefore, as this key-stone is removed from the human
mind, it falls a prey to discord and the isolation of its several powers; nay
more, the latter sink continually lower and lower, and fall from one depth of
degradation to another. And when occasionally, as in the might and strength
of genius, there occurs a preponderance of some one faculty, it exercises for
the most part a destructive tendency against the harmony of the whole,
checking, if not suppressing altogether, the free developments of other
powers as necessary and as essential as itself.
42. LECTURE VI.
ACCORDING to that outline of the human mind which we have just
sketched, its whole alphabet, so to speak, consists but of twelve letters or
primary elements. These are formed first of all into the stem-syllables or
radicals of higher truth and knowledge, out of which again, in the inner
language of true science, entire words and connected propositions are
constructed. And these again must further combine into one universal key
and all-embracing fundamental word of life. In this internal alphabet of the
consciousness, however, there is one point on which a few words of further
explanation are necessary to a right understanding. And it is one of the very
highest consequence, since it concerns the final aim or even the first
foundation, being nothing less than the center of life and perfection of unity.
God, it is said, must form the key-stone in the arch of the whole
consciousness; and no other real point of union can be found. But now God
is without, or, rather, above, the human mind. How, then, are we to
designate that by and through which this center of unity, which we feel and
acknowledge to be raised far above us, is to be seized and retained, so that it
may livingly operate within us? I know no other way of indicating it than
by the word idea—the idea, viz., of the divine and of the Divinity Himself.
As, then, feeling forms the common center of life for the lower and ordinary
consciousness of man and its eight elementary faculties, so it is this idea
that, as the third internal principle, makes up, together with spirit and soul,
the higher threefold living consciousness. But by this idea we mean not a
merely speculative or abstract and dead idea, but an effectually operative
and living idea of a God, who, having life in Himself, is the source from
which all life proceeds. In its outward form, and as compared with the other
functions of the consciousness or acts of the thinking faculty, this idea is a
notion. At the same time, however, it is also a figure or a symbol. For it is
only figuratively that that which is not so much inconceivable, as rather
transcends conception, being far above and beyond all possible notions, can
be at all indicated. It is by symbols alone that such can be conceived or
comprehended. Indeed, the word idea, in its original Greek sense, alludes to
some kind of visible figure and figurative shape lying, as it were, within the
notion itself. All that is highest of every species can only be apprehended by
such a mode of thinking as is at the same time both logical and symbolical
—in which the logical thought of reason and the symbolical of imagination
—the scientific, viz., or of that which in cognition is the inward productive
43. faculty, are once more in unison, being thoroughly combined or wholly
blended together. The idea, however, is not merely a conception, which is a
notion, and yet, at the same time, as properly transcending all notion, a
figure or symbol; but looking to the inward form of the consciousness,
rather than to the object itself, it is a conception which is also a feeling.
Indeed, without the supposition of the latter it can not exist, and, strictly
speaking, is not even conceivable. That this is the case, the following
instance will fully show: How could we, if we wished it, suggest the idea of
true love, or make it clear and comprehensible to one who had never felt
any thing of the kind, and was, in short, totally incapable of such a feeling?
Properly, however, and in scientific rigor, there is only one idea truly so
called. And that is the one idea of the Godhead. All else that we call ideas,
whether in this higher signification, or in a kindred and similar sense—like
the innate ideas, without number, of which the Platonic philosophy speaks,
or that idea of true love which I lately alluded to (having previously made
frequent use of such expressions, and intending to do so again whenever
they appear calculated to lead to accuracy of distinction or vividness of
indication)—all such can only be called ideas in a certain sense and
analogy. Such a mode of speech, however, is allowable whenever we are
treating of such notions and conceptions as stand in any relation to the
higher and divine. For, contemplated from this spiritual center of the divine
idea, they shine in a new light. Being purified in its flame, they seem to be
elevated and brought many degrees nearer to this one supreme idea of the
living God, in all His perfection and beauty. In all its fullness and
completeness, however, this idea can not truly be said to be innate in the
human mind. At most there are there only the elements of it, viz., the
remembrance of eternal love (which Plato’s doctrine of the anamnesis,
when purified, amounts to), the infinite longing, the voice of conscience;
and then, completing the number, as the fourth element, comes the genuine
and exalted enthusiasm for art and natural beauty. All these higher elements,
however, of the divine in man, form but a weak echo of the whole. They
are, as it were, but so many faint dying notes, or the first infantine lispings
of this one divine idea, which in its full force and brightness must be given,
imparted, and revealed; while that which is thus given and experienced, and
indeed personally experienced, can only be embraced, understood, and
retained by faith through love.
44. He who has never had any feeling or experience of God, who is a
stranger to love, and incapable of faith of any kind, to such a one, so long as
he remains in this state, it would be lost labor to speak of God, or of the
divine idea, with all that flows immediately from it. This idea may indeed
exist as a rational notion necessarily emanating from our own cogitations.
But in this form, as the creature of our own conception, but not as a given
and revealed, it is little better than the fixed reflection of ourselves—the
objective projection of our own Me. For such in all purely rational systems
it ever is—emptied and utterly void of all effectual living power, and of all
truth and reality. But when the idea of God has been received by a higher
experience (and thus only can it be vitally imparted), then may we in truth
call it divine. For it is no longer the barren, unfruitful idea that it is in all
other cases, but it contains in itself an effectual living and life-giving
energy.
The fundamental elements of the human consciousness are, then, twelve
in number. The first universal basis is formed by the eight special faculties,
with love as their living center. To these must be added the three principles
of the higher inward life—soul, spirit, and the idea of the divine—such as
we have accurately defined and characterized it. These together I have
called the alphabet of the consciousness. And this alphabet, like a fixed and
established logical notion, I shall henceforth adopt in this precise shape and
number, making it, without any essential variation, the basis of my
subsequent remarks. It is, no doubt, of great advantage, and even necessary
for the elucidation of any matter, rigorously to separate the several elements
of the general notion, duly arranging them, and accurately preserving their
number. Still we may be overanxious in this respect. And, indeed, language
itself is not always very precise in its designations; and the different dialects
of human speech, with their fluctuating phraseology, often assign a different
rank and position to the parts of the same whole. Much, for instance is set
down as an independent faculty, which, more correctly regarded, is but a
state—or even only a passage from one state into another—or it may be
merely a natural talent; or, perhaps, some such happy coincidence and
harmonious co-operation of several powers of the soul as constitutes true
genius. An instance of this kind gave rise to that question which so lately
engaged our attention, whether the judgment is rightly to be considered a
special faculty; and, if not, how is it in strictness of truth to be designated?
And in a similar respect, I now find occasion to say a few words on wit, as
45. being nearly related to judgment (if the latter be, as I have explained it, an
intelligent feeling), and as holding an intermediate position between
judgment and genius. For now we have given a complete sketch in outline
of the whole consciousness, it is desirable to fill in, as completely as
possible, all the lesser and nicer features. In other words, it is expedient to
assign their proper place in the entire consciousness to those properties of
soul and spirit which are not so much simple or first principles as complex
phenomena of a secondary order, and compounded of several distinct
elements. Now wit, like judgment, is an intelligent feeling, marked,
however, with the qualities of immediateness and pertinency. But it is not,
like the judgment, associated always with a special knowledge and insight.
On the contrary, wit often arises from a certain naïve ignorance of the entire
province to which belongs the object on which it exercises itself. We might
almost say that the disposition to wit consists in a universally intelligent
feeling, for its quickness of perception is confined to no particular
department of life, but exercises itself on life in general, and finds therein
its proper arena. But this describes rather the notion of what is commonly
called “sound sense,” or “natural intelligence,” which, in itself, is not wit,
and is often found existing totally unaccompanied with the latter.
Nevertheless, this at least is manifest, that if an individual be said to be
entirely devoid of judgment—which is nearly the same as saying that he
possesses no intelligent feeling in any species or form—it would be in vain
in such a person to look for much, if any, wit. That, moreover, which forms
the chief characteristic of wit, and essentially distinguishes it from
judgment, is its unconsciousness. On this very account children even, if
they be at all lively, are often witty. And, indeed, this childish wit forms,
perhaps, one of the most graceful of its many forms and kinds. To prove
how greatly this childish wit depends on its very unconsciousness, we may
appeal to a fact, which, moreover, will teach us at the same time not to lay
too much stress on the fact, if children, even at an early age, appear very
clever and witty. It is no unfrequent observation that when children, by the
development of their understandings, attain to greater clearness of
consciousness, their wit suddenly ceases, and their character assumes a
touch of dry, solemn, but still childish earnestness. That genial
unconsciousness which ever remains the property of true wit, both of social
conversation and of poetry, at once forms and attests its affinity with genius.
But, still, wit alone is not a complete creative power. By itself it rarely gives
46. birth to aught. It is but a single element, which is added as the last finishing
grace to all the creative productions of fancy, and to every other work in
which a fertile and original mind gives utterance to its thoughts. On this
account it manifests itself in the most varied and opposite forms. It is not
limited to social conversation, or to art and poetry, but even in philosophy
—and the Socratic especially—assumes a peculiar and important place as
the essential ingredient of irony.
Now the variety of forms in which wit so richly displays itself is a
further point of resemblance between it and judgment. Still this common
property has a different cause in each. The immediate judgment, or
intelligent feeling, presents so great a variety of forms, because the human
mind is not equally conversant in every province of thought, being
generally familiar with some one in particular. But in the case of wit, it is its
very versatility, by which it suits itself to and insinuates itself in every
object of intellectual attention, that is the source of its manifold diversity.
But that it would carry us far beyond our present limits, it would be highly
instructive in a scientific point of view to take a survey of all the several
forms in which this mental quality gushes forth in all the rich fullness of
genius.
But now, since our exposition of the human mind has been hitherto
carried on by means of a parallelism with the idea of language, it will not be
out of place to make a few remarks here on the real alphabet, or the
elementary letters of different languages, as bearing a relation to what we
have called the alphabet of the consciousness. For the former presents more
than one remarkable analogy with the higher principle of the inward life,
and its whole organic framework. Properly, syllables, and not letters, form
the basis of language. They are its living roots, or chief stem and trunk, out
of which all else shoots and grows. The letters, in fact, have no existence,
except as the results of a minute analysis; for many of them are difficult, if
not impossible, to pronounce. Syllables, on the contrary, more or less
simple, or the complex composites of fewer or more letters, are the primary
and original data of language. For the synthetical is in every case anterior to
the elements into which it admits of resolution. The letters, therefore, first
arise out of the chemical decomposition of the syllables. But the results of
this analytical process are very different in different languages, as is proved
by the difference of results in the variety of alphabets. While in our own we
reckon four-and-twenty letters, in many others the number is far greater. In
47. those oriental languages nearest akin to our own, they amount to more than
thirty; while the Indian family counts as many as fifty.
It forms no easy problem to indicate most of these by our European
characters; and to pronounce them requires the organs of speech to be more
than ordinarily flexible. On the other hand, profound and philosophical
inquires into language, by rejecting all mere modifications of harshness or
softness in the same sound, and whatever is manifestly a mere variation of
the same letter, or a mere compound of simpler tones, have reduced the
whole alphabet to ten primary elements. According to this system, which
has not been established without great acuteness, so much at least is
evident, that properly there are but three vowels,[70] instead of five, as we
usually count them, the E being a softened I, and U a deadened or faint O.
The diphthongs, and other tones intermediate between the simple vowels, in
which the German is so rich, are evidently to be considered but as so many
musical transitions from one to the other. We may here appeal to the
Hebrew, as being in its system of letters, notwithstanding its other ancient
oriental features, highly simple and profoundly significant and coherent.[71]
Its two-and-twenty characters may be divided into two orders. The first and
higher, as I would term it, contains the three vowels, the aspirates (of which
more by and by), and then the simplest and softest (they might almost be
called the child’s) consonants, B, D, G. The twelve letters of the second
contain all the other grosser, more corporeally-sounding consonants.
Usually, indeed, all letters, and especially consonants, are classed into
labials, linguals, and dentals, according to the organs principally employed
in their utterance, distinguishing, on the same principle, certain nasals and
gutturals. But however correct this classification may be in an anatomical
point of view, and physiologically considered, still, for that parallel, which
is grounded in nature itself, between speech and thought, and for the
analogy which subsists between man’s inward and outward language, it is
both unsatisfactory and uninstructive. For it looks exclusively to a single
aspect. The ordinary grammatical division also of letters into vowels and
consonants, is at least incomplete. It would be far more correct to associate
with them a third class of aspirates. For the latter may be distinguished from
the former by many a characteristic property, even though they are indicated
by signs which resemble those of the other class and often pass into and
may be resolved into them. In the various alphabetical systems the aspirates
stand out most individually. They assume the most diversified forms, even
48. in their mode of notation, and it would almost seem as if the ethereal
breathing which floats around them refused to be corporeally fixed and
confined with as much easiness as the other elements of language. In some
languages, as the Greek, for instance, according to the extant system, which
belongs not to the earliest period of its development, the principal aspiration
is not denoted by a letter, but is indicated in the same way as an accent. In
the oriental, and, generally, in all ancient languages, the aspirates, according
to the different forms into which they enter, hold a very important place. It
almost seems that the more aspirated a language is, the nearer it is to its
original state. It is also remarkable, that wherever this element appears in
undiminished vigor, it gives to the whole language a character of antiquity
and grandeur, and lends to it a pervading tone of spiritual gravity, such as
has been observed in the Arabic, and prevails also in a high degree in the
Spanish; though, indeed, an undue prevalence of this high and solemn note,
unrelieved by others, is apt to degenerate into monotony. In our own
German the aspirates were originally far more numerous than they are at
present. And, generally, the more a language is softened down and refined
by daily use and conversation, the more it loses this impress of antiquity.
And it even happens with some, as with the French, for instance, that the
aspirates cease to be articulated, even though they are still marked.
Now, while the aspirates form the spiritual element in the whole system
of elementary sounds, in the vowels, on the other hand, predominates the
soul-full voice of song. These, in short, form the musical ensouling
principle of language. The less a language is overladen with consonants,
and the more fully the simple vowels sound out, the better adapted is it for
music and songs. The consonants, on the other hand, which only in part
imitate sound, make up the material element of language. They are, no
doubt, necessary to the richness of a language, and its variety of expression;
nevertheless, when they greatly predominate, they render it corporeal and
heavy.
Now this remarkable analogy between this division of the alphabet into
aspirates, vowels, and consonants, and the triple principle of human life and
operation, as consisting of spirit, of soul, and of body, or of bodily exterior,
I could not but notice in passing, and throw out as distinctly as possible.
But now this analogy and parallel between speech and consciousness
presents another view of the matter, which it appears desirable to consider.
In the alphabet of the human consciousness, which furnishes the several
49. elements out of which syllables and then words are framed, which again
form the first elements of all man’s higher knowledge, I would pre-
eminently consider as its vowels those eternal feelings of the Godlike which
have their foundation in the very nature of man. Now it is usual to designate
these fundamental feelings of man as faith, hope, and love (charity). But,
however customary it may be to class the three together, the intrinsic
connection between them is not easily pointed out. And yet, perhaps, if we
have recourse to another analogy with the visible world, it will help us to
trace this bond of union. This method will probably be both easier and
simpler than a direct refutation of erroneous views on the subject, or any
critical enumeration of elements which in the psychological apprehension
are incorrectly associated with them. Now, these three feelings or
properties, or states of the consciousness, may be regarded as so many
organs for the cognition or the perception, or, if the term be preferred, for
the suggestion of the divine. In this respect, then, and relatively to their
different modes of apprehension, we may compare them with the external
senses and their organs. Thus love, in its first soul-exciting contact, abiding
attraction, and finally complete union, strikingly corresponds to the external
sense of feeling. Faith is the inner ear of the spirit which is open to, catches
up, and retains the imparted word of a higher revelation. Hope, however, is
the eye, whose clear vision discerns, even in the remote distance, the
objects of its profound and ardent longing. The latter brings us to a
thoroughly vivid idea (or, rather, presupposes the existence) of faith,
according to which it is no arbitrary and artificial idea, but one real
throughout and vital. Although intelligent and spiritual, it is still a feeling,
and ultimately rests also on a feeling, that, viz., of love, out of which, as its
root and foundation, it arises. Indeed, faith is nothing else than love,
through a pure will, maintained with consistency of character; and this
applies to it even in its nobler relations among human things, and does not
apply to it merely in a higher and divine reference.
In the last age (if it be not also in the present), the notion of faith was
taken in a very different sense, and the phraseology arising from that view
is, in part, at least, still prevalent. On this account a few explanatory words
are necessary for the sake of caution and distinction. The following is the
historical occasion or scientific origin of this other notion of faith. At a late
period of so-called enlightenment, in the midst of which, however, many
grave misconceptions prevailed, reason was set up as the sole authority. As
50. the highest and greatest of man’s endowments, it was almost deified,
whatever did not appear at once and easily explicable by reason, being
forthwith and indiscriminately pronounced a prejudice, and, as such, to be
got rid of with all diligence. In this state of things, modern German
philosophy commenced its career with attempting to show that this
sovereign reason, which had set itself forth as the first and highest in man,
is extremely defective, and comes far short of the requisitions both of
science and life. The position was honestly and earnestly maintained, and
the proof worked out with tolerable completeness. Subsequently, however,
its validity has been questioned, or only admitted under many limitations
and qualifications. But even this modified praise can not be bestowed on the
scientific remedy with which men hoped to supply the defects of reason,
and to cure the old and universal evils of rationalism. For, in fact, the
method by which they sought to get rid of this great and manifest deficiency
was simply by suddenly opening an unlimited credit for the reason, which
going beyond all actual need, and based either on arbitrary assumption, or a
confiding generosity, should be sufficient for all emergencies. But this
expedient, in the existing state and panic of the rational market, could not
remove the evil; it only exaggerated it. In a word, it was the same old
reason which (its claim to supersensible honors having been rejected) had
been just thrust out of the temple of science by the front entrance, that,
under the disguise of faith, was now being smuggled in by the postern. It
was but a mere arbitrary substitute for reason that had assumed this new
name. Now such a faith as this requires to be carefully distinguished from
that living faith which springs from and is founded on love. For this
purpose I have attempted to show, from the very outset, the great difference
between the two.
Now, if occasionally I have felt myself called upon to set bounds to and
to protest against the illimitable requirements and assumptions of reason in
science, my remarks have been directed, not against reason itself, but
chiefly against that absoluteness with which it pretends to reign paramount.
In our German tongue—and since the comparative parallel of thought and
language is a part of the general plan of our present exposition, this trifling
but not insignificant philological remark will not here be inappropriate—in
our vernacular tongue, the close limitation of the thing is furnished by the
term itself. For as understanding [Verstand] comes from the verb to
understand [verstehen], and implies the existence of an object which stands
51. before the mind, to be penetrated and searched through by it, so reason
[Vernunft] implies a Vernehmen, a perception or apprehension, and is itself
nothing else than the organ of spiritual perception, which is threefold: 1st,
of a higher law and rule above us and given to us; 2d, of the inward voice of
conscience and the pure self-consciousness within us; and, 3d, of other
rational thought around and beside itself. Now it is only against that reason
which is unwilling to perceive any thing, or, at least, any thing beside or
above itself, that all my objections are directed. For when the reason refuses
to acknowledge aught above itself, but absolutely rejects it, then will it
estimate but little whatever is beside itself. At any rate it will never be
eminently successful in its attempts to comprehend or understand it. In this
case, it will continually make the greatest mistakes and blunders in its views
and conceptions of that even which it really finds and perceives, or at least
believes to discover within itself. Reason, in itself, and in its due limits, is,
indeed, but one of man’s various fundamental powers; still, in the present
state of his divided and discordant consciousness, it is a highly essential
faculty. Like all the others, consequently, which severally do but present so
many different aspects of man’s external and internal life, reason, when it
oversteps its due limits, is liable to great, nay, the greatest of aberrations.
But it might here be asked, are not the possible aberrations of fancy still
more dangerous? We must answer, Without doubt they are; and this is the
only answer we can give to the question put thus generally. But in the
special reference to our own age, there is far greater and more frequent
occasion to call attention at present to the evils produced by the errors of
reason, than to warn men anxiously against the possible abuses of fancy.
And this for the simple fact, that of all the powers of the human mind,
which, when isolated, are, more or less, destructive in their action, reason
has, in the later ages, and in our times, especially, been decidedly
predominant. Consequently, we have on all sides before our eyes obvious
and instructive examples of the mazes and abyss of error, fatal no less to
science than to morals, into which reason not only falls herself, but hurries
all that come within her influence, when, having once started from a false
position, she has followed out this wrong tendency with full rigor of
consequence. We see in it the cause of all the catastrophes of the age, and
the fearful struggle of party. The dangers which might arise from the
exclusive ascendency of fancy are, in our generation, less likely to be
general, and they are less threatening, less urgent. And the explanation of
52. Welcome to our website – the perfect destination for book lovers and
knowledge seekers. We believe that every book holds a new world,
offering opportunities for learning, discovery, and personal growth.
That’s why we are dedicated to bringing you a diverse collection of
books, ranging from classic literature and specialized publications to
self-development guides and children's books.
More than just a book-buying platform, we strive to be a bridge
connecting you with timeless cultural and intellectual values. With an
elegant, user-friendly interface and a smart search system, you can
quickly find the books that best suit your interests. Additionally,
our special promotions and home delivery services help you save time
and fully enjoy the joy of reading.
Join us on a journey of knowledge exploration, passion nurturing, and
personal growth every day!
ebookbell.com